Skip to main content

Intergenerational Equity, Efficiency, and Constructibility

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Studies in Economic Theory ((ECON.THEORY,volume 29))

Abstract

Global environmental issues—like biodiversity conservation or climate change—are in reality long term issues that are not properly taken into account with traditional models that incorporate the impatience axiom manifested in fixed discount factors and in the use of present discounted utility criteria. When both the short and the very long run are important, one can appeal to overtaking criteria and Chichilnisky criteria. Unfortunately, overtaking criteria are highly incomplete. In order to decrease this incompleteness, stronger anonymity (or equity) axioms were developed. I show that a maximal anonymity axiom compatible with Pareto is a non-constructible object; its existence relies on the Axiom of Choice. The Chichilnisky criterion is based upon two axioms: non dictatorship of the present and non dictatorship of the future. Here, the very long run is captured by a finitely additive measure. Such a measure is a non-constructible object and has therefore no explicit description.

I thank Norbert Brunner, Graciela Chichilnisky, Koen Decancq, Marc Fleurbaey, Johan Quaegebeur, and Luc Van Liedekerke for helpful conversations. I am grateful for the many constructive comments by the referee. A first version was presented at the workshop “Intergenerational equity in climate negotiations, overlapping generations and social welfare” organized by Claude d’Aspremont and Thierry Bréchet (CORE, April 27–28, 2006). This text presents research results of the Belgian Programme of Interuniversity Poles of Attraction initiated under the Science Policy Programmes of the Prime Minister’s Office, Belgium. The scientific responsibility is assumed by its authors.

Originally published in Economic Theory, Volume 49, Number 2, February 2012 DOI 10.1007/s00199-010-0573-7.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    An evaluation F of infinite utility streams is said to be normalized if \(F(r,r,\ldots ,r,\ldots ) = r\) for each r in \(\mathbb {R}\). Due to this normalization the discounted sum is premultiplied with \((1-\beta )\).

  2. 2.

    This conclusion extends to, for example, the widely used Dasgupta-Heal-Solow growth model.

  3. 3.

    Asheim (2010) provides an excellent survey.

  4. 4.

    Consider the streams \(w=(1,-1,-1,1;1,-1,-1,1;\ldots ;1,-1,-1,1;\ldots )\) and \(z=(0,0,\ldots ,0,\ldots )\). The overtaking criterion is unable to rank w and z. An utilitarian overtaking criterion that satisfies fixed step anonymity considers w and z equally good.

  5. 5.

    A welfare function displays ‘dictatorship of the present’ if it is insensitive for changes that affect the distinct future. A welfare function displays ‘dictatorship of the future’ if it is insensitive for changes that do not affect the limiting behavior criterion.

  6. 6.

    Burniaux and Martins (2011), Chipman and Tian (2011), Dutta and Radner (2011), Karp and Zhang (2011), and Ostrom (2011) tackle the question of how to implement policies that respect the interests of future generations and to assess their effectiveness in the context of global externalities with long-lasting effects. Lecocq and Hourcade (2011) argue that optimal policies may require estimates of future intragenerational distributions. Rezai et al. (2011) show that, in some cases, such policies may benefit all generations.

  7. 7.

    Purely finitely additive measures are typically obtained via non-constructive mathematics (Hahn-Banach’s theorem or ultrafilters, cf. Chichilnisky 2009a, 2011). This observation can be strengthened: it is impossible to create a purely finitely additive measure on \({\mathbb {N}_0}\) without recurse to non-constructive methods.

  8. 8.

    The map \(\liminf \) (see Sect. 2.1) is not additive: \(\liminf (1,0,1,0,\ldots )= \liminf (0,1,0,1,\ldots )=0\); while \(\liminf [(1,0,1,0,\ldots )+ (0,1,0,1,\ldots )]= \liminf (1,1,1,1,\ldots ) =1\).

  9. 9.

    AC is (i) consistent and (ii) independent: (i) AC can be added to the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms of set theory (ZF) without yielding a contradiction, and (ii) AC is not a theorem of ZF (Fraenkel et al. 1973).

  10. 10.

    The law of the excluded middle states the truth of ‘P or not-P’ for each proposition P and can be used to claim the existence of certain objects without any hint to its construction. For example, the real number \(c={\scriptstyle \sqrt{2}}^{\,{\sqrt{2}}}\) either is rational (in which case one sets \(a=b=\sqrt{2}\,\)) or is not rational (in which case one sets \(a=c\) and \(b=\sqrt{2}\)). Conclude the existence of irrational numbers a and b for which \(a^b\) is rational.

  11. 11.

    In this example, \(\liminf (s_t)\) is the limit of the sequence 1 / 9, 11 / 99, \(111/999,\ldots \) and is equal to 1/9; \(\limsup (s_t)\) is the limit of the sequence 1, 11 / 19, \(111/199,\ldots \) and is equal to 5/9.

References

  • Alvarez-Cuadrado, F., & Van Long, N. (2009). A mixed Bentham-Rawls criterion for intergenerational equity: Theory and implications. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 58, 154–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B. (2010). Intergenerational equity. Annual Review of Economics, 2, 197–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B., d’Aspremont, C., & Banerjee, K. (2016). Generalized time-invariant overtaking. Journal of Mathematical Economics,. doi:10.1016/j.jmateco.2010.03.005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B., & Banerjee, K. (2010). Fixed-step anonymous overtaking and catching up. International Journal of Economic Theory, 6, 149–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B., & Mitra, T. (2010). Sustainability and discounted utilitarianism in models of economic growth. Mathematical Social Sciences, 59, 148–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B., Mitra, T., & Tungodden, B. (2011). Sustainable recursive social welfare functions. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume ). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0573-7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ax, J. (1968). The elementary theory of finite fields. Annals of Mathematics, 88, 239–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee, K. (2006). On the extension of the utilitarian and Suppes-Sen social welfare relations to infinite utility streams. Social Choice and Welfare, 27, 327–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burniaux, J.-M., & Martins, J. O. (2011). Carbon leakages: A general equilibrium view. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0598-y.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, C. P. (2009). Intergenerational equity: sup, inf, \(\limsup \), and \(\liminf \). Social Choice and Welfare, 32, 243–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G. (1996). An axiomatic approach to sustainable development. Social Choice and Welfare, 13, 231–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G. (2009a). The topology of fear. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 45, 807–816.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G. (2009b). Avoiding extinction: Equal treatment of the present and the future. The Open-Access, Open-Assessment E-Journal, 3, 2009–2032.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G. (2011). Sustainable markets with short sales. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume).

    Google Scholar 

  • Chipman, J. S., & Tian, G. (2011). Detrimental externalities, pollution rights, and the “Coase theorem”. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-011-0602-1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dianonescu, R. (1975). Axiom of choice and complementation. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 51, 176–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta, P. K., & Radner, R. (2011). Capital growth in a global warming model: will China and India sign a climate treaty? Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0590-6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Figuières, C., & Tidball, M. (2011). Sustainable exploitation of a natural resource: a satisfying use of Chichilnisky’s criterion. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0579-1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey, M., & Michel, P. (2003). Intertemporal equity and the extension of the Ramsey criterion. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 39, 777–802.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fraenkel, A. A., Bar-Hillel, Y., & Levy, A. (1973). Foundation of Set Theory. Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halbeisen, L., & Löwe, B. (2001). Ultrafilter spaces on the semilattice of partitions. Topology and its Applications, 115, 317–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, M, Jr. (1976). The theory of groups. New York: Chelsea Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heal, G. M. (1998). Valuing the future: Economic theory and sustainability. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jech, T. J. (1973). The axiom of choice. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamaga, K., & Kojima, T. (2009a). \({\cal{Q}}\)-anonymous social welfare relations on infinite utility streams. Social Choice and Welfare, 33, 405–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamaga, K., & Kojima, T. (2009b). On the leximin and utilitarian criteria with extended anonymity. Tokyo, Japan: Waseda University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karp, L., & Zhang, J. (2011). Taxes versus quantities for a stock pollutant with endogenous abatement costs and asymmetric information. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0561-y.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers, L. (1997). Infinite utility: Insisting on strong monotonicity. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 75, 222–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers., L. (2010a). Ordering infinite utility streams comes at the cost of a non-Ramsey set. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 46, 32–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers, L. (2010b). Purely finitely additive measures are non-constructible objects. K.U.Leuven: DPS 1010 Center for Economic Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lecocq, F., & Hourcade, J.-C. (2011). Unspoken ethical issues in the climate affair, insights from a theoretical analysis of negotiation mandates. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0589-z.

    Google Scholar 

  • Li, C.-Z., & Löfgren, K.-G. (2000). Renewable resources and economic sustainability: A dynamic analysis with heterogeneous time preferences. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 40, 236–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mathias, A. R. D. (1977). Happy families. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 12, 59–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitra, T., & Basu, K. (2007). On the existence of Paretian social welfare relations for infinite utility streams with extended anonymity. In J. Roemer & K. Suzumura (Eds.), Intergenerational equity and sustainability (pp. 85–99). London: Palgrave.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (2011). Nested externalities and polycentric institutions: Must we wait for global solutions to climate change before taking actions at other scales? Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0558-6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rao, R. R. (1958). A note on finitely additive measures. Indian Journal of Statistics, 19, 27–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rezai, A., Foley, D. K., & Taylor, L. (2011). Global warming and economic externalities. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0592-4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yosida, K., & Hewitt, E. (1952). Finitely additive measures. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 72, 46–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zame, W. (2007). Can intergenerational equity be operationalized? Theoretical Economics, 2, 187–202.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luc Lauwers .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lauwers, L. (2016). Intergenerational Equity, Efficiency, and Constructibility. In: Chichilnisky, G., Rezai, A. (eds) The Economics of the Global Environment. Studies in Economic Theory, vol 29. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-31943-8_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics