Skip to main content

Semantic Nominalism: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Universals

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Objectivity, Realism, and Proof

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 318))

  • 541 Accesses

Abstract

Aldo Antonelli offers a novel view on abstraction principles in order to solve a traditional tension between different requirements: that the claims of science be taken at face value, even when involving putative reference to mathematical entities; and that referents of mathematical terms are identified and their possible relations to other objects specified. In his view, abstraction principles provide representatives for equivalence classes of second-order entities that are available provided the first- and second-order domains are in the equilibrium dictated by the abstraction principles, and whose choice is otherwise unconstrained. Abstract entities are the referents of abstraction terms: such referents are to an extent indeterminate, but we can still quantify over them, predicate identity or non-identity, etc. Our knowledge of them is limited, but still substantial: we know whatever has to be true no matter how the representatives are chosen, i.e., what is true in all models of the corresponding abstraction principles. This view is backed up by an “austere” conception of universals, according to which these are first-order objects, i.e., ways of collecting first-order objects. Antonelli thus claims that second-order logic does not import any novel ontological commitment beyond ontology of first-order, naturalistically acceptable, objects. Moreover, in the case of arithmetic, even if Hume’s Principle is construed as described above, Frege’s Theorem goes through unaffected, since there is nothing in its proof that depends on an account of the “true nature” of numbers. A viable construal of logicism is then given by the combination of semantic nominalism and a naturalistic conception of abstraction. [Editors note]

I am grateful to Tyrus Fisher and Elaine Landry for valuable comments and criticism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Antonelli, G. A. (2010a). The nature and purpose of numbers. Journal of Philosophy, 107(4), 191–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antonelli, G. A. (2010b). Notions of invariance for abstraction principles. Philosophia Mathematica, 18(3), 276–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antonelli, G. A. (2010c). Numerical abstraction via the Frege quantifier. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 51(2), 161–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antonelli, G. A. (2012). A note on induction, abstraction, and Dedekind-finiteness. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 53(2), 187–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antonelli, G. A. (2013). On the general interpretation of first-order quantifiers. Review of Symbolic Logic, 6(4), 637–658.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antonelli, G. A. (2015). Life on the range: Quine’s thesis and semantic indeterminacy. In A. Torza (Ed.), Quantifiers, quantifiers, and quantifiers: Themes in logic, metaphysics, and language, synthese library 373 (pp. 171–189). Chan: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antonelli, G. A., & May, R. (2012). A note on order. In T. Graf, D. Paperno, A. Szabolcsi, & J. Tellings (Eds.), Theories of everything: in honor of Ed Keenan, UCLA Working Papers in Linguistics. (Vol. 17, pp. 1–6).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. (1973). Mathematical truth. Journal of Philosophy, 70(19), 661–679.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonnay, D. (2008). Logicality and invariance. Bullettin of Symbolic Logic, 14(1), 29–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgess, J., & Rosen, G. (2005). Nominalism reconsidered. In S. Shapiro (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mathematics and logic (Chap. 16, pp. 515–535) Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butts, R., & Hintikka, J. (Ed.). (1977). Logic, foundations of mathematics, and computability theory. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dedekind, R. (1988). Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen, Vieweg: Braunschweig, 1888, English translation, (The Nature and Meaning of Numbers. In R. Dedekind, Essays on the theory of numbers, Dover: New York. pp. 29–115.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1991). Frege: philosophy of mathematics. Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feferman, S. (1977). Categorical foundations and foundations of category theory. In R. E. Butts & J. Hintikka (Eds.), Logic, foundations of mathematics, and computability theory, The University of Western Ontario series in philosophy of science (Vol. 9, pp. 149–169). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1980). Science without numbers. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1989). Realism, mathematics and modality. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Florio, S., & Linnebo, Ø. (forthcoming). On the innocence and determinacy of plural quantification. Noûs doi:10.1111/nous.12091

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1980). The foundations of arithmetic: A logico-mathematical enquiry into the concept of number. (J. L. Austin, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N., & Quine, W. V. (1947). Steps toward a constructive nominalism. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 12(4), 105–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B., & Wright, C. (2001). To bury Caesar. In B. Hale & C. Wright, The reason’s proper study (pp. 355–396). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. (2001). Is platonism epistemologically bankrupt? In B. Hale & C. Wright, The reason’s proper study (pp. 169–188). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Originally in The Philosophical Review, 103(2), 299–325 (1994).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, G. (1989). Mathematics without numbers: towards a modal-structural interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (1998). On higher-order logic and natural language. In T. Smiley (Ed.), Philosophical Logic, Proceedings of the British Academy (Vol. 95, pp. 1–27).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilary, P. (1971). Philosophy of Logic. New York: Harper essays in philosophy, Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weierstraß, K. (1854). Zur Theorie Der Abelschen Functionen. Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik, 47, 289–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1991). Parts of classes. Hoboken: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Panza, M., & Sereni, A. (2013). Plato’s problem: An introduction to mathematical platonism. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, S., & Westerståhl, D. (2006). Quantifiers in language and logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. (1971). P. T. Geach & A. J. P. Kenny (Eds.), Objects of thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1951). Ontology and ideology. Philosophical Studies, 2(1), 11–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (1993). The refutation of nominalism (?). Philosophical Topics, 21(2), 141–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1918–1919). The philosophy of logical atomism. The Monist, 28 and 29: 495–527 (part I) and 33–63 (part II).

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1986). What are logical notions?. History and Philosophy of Logic, 7(2), 143–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1983). Frege’s conception of numbers as objects. Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Antonelli, G.A. (2016). Semantic Nominalism: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Universals. In: Boccuni, F., Sereni, A. (eds) Objectivity, Realism, and Proof . Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 318. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-31644-4_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics