Skip to main content

The Enactive Philosophy of Embodiment: From Biological Foundations of Agency to the Phenomenology of Subjectivity

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Biology and Subjectivity

Abstract

Following the philosophy of embodiment of Merleau-Ponty, Jonas and others, enactivism is a pivot point from which various areas of science can be brought into a fruitful dialogue about the nature of subjectivity. In this chapter we present the enactive conception of agency, which, in contrast to current mainstream theories of agency, is deeply and strongly embodied. In line with this thinking we argue that anything that ought to be considered a genuine agent is a biologically embodied (even if distributed) agent, and that this embodiment must be affectively lived. However, we also consider that such an affective agent is not necessarily also an agent imbued with an explicit sense of subjectivity. To support this contention we outline the interoceptive foundation of basic agency and argue that there is a qualitative difference in the phenomenology of agency when it is instantiated in organisms which, due to their complexity and size, require a nervous system to underpin their physiological and sensorimotor processes. We argue that this interoceptively grounded agency not only entails affectivity but also forms the necessary basis for subjectivity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Stylistic note: we cite the most recent English edition of our sources whenever this is possible for ease of reference. However, in order to avoid giving a false impression of the original date of publication, we also always provide the year of publication of the first edition in square brackets.

  2. 2.

    The attribution of subjecthood by others may in fact be an essential element in infants’ development of an explicit awareness of their own subjectivity (Reddy 2003), but on the view we are promoting here they were already agents on their own terms even before they were born. This is what allows much of the body schema to develop in utero rather than post-partum (Lymer 2011).

References

  • Arnellos, A., and A. Moreno. 2015. Multicellular agency: An organizational view. Biology and Philosophy 30(3): 333–357.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X., E.A. Di Paolo, and M. Rohde. 2009. Defining agency: individuality, normativity, asymmetry, and spatio-temporality in action. Adaptive Behavior 17(5): 367–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X., and M.D. Egbert. 2014. Norm-establishing and norm-following in autonomous agency. Artificial Life 20(1): 5–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X., and A. Moreno. 2006. On what makes certain dynamical systems cognitive: A minimally cognitive organization program. Adaptive Behavior 14(2): 171–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X., and A. Moreno. 2008. Adaptivity: From metabolism to behavior. Adaptive Behavior 16(5): 325–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barbaras, R. 2002. Francisco Varela: A new idea of perception and life. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 127–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barbaras, R. 2005. Desire and distance: Introduction to a phenomenology of perception. Trans. P.B. Milan. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbaras, R. 2010. Life and exteriority: The problem of metabolism. In Enaction: Toward a new paradigm for cognitive science, ed. J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, and E.A. Di Paolo. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R.D. 2000. Dynamical approaches to cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4(3): 91–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bower, M., and S. Gallagher. 2013. Bodily affects as prenoetic elements in enactive perception. Phenomenology and Mind 4(1): 108–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, O.G. 2001. Interoception: The inside story—A model for psychosomatic processes. Psychosomatic Medicine 63(5): 697–710.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 1989. Microfunctionalism: Connectionism and the scientific explanation of mental states. Research paper. Retrieved July 17, 2011. http://www.era.lib.ed.ac.uk/handle/1842/1332.

  • Clark, A. 1997. Being there: Putting brain, body and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 1999. An embodied cognitive science? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 3(9): 345–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. 2007. Enactive appraisal. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6: 527–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. 2010. Enaction, sense-making, and emotion. In Enaction: Toward a new paradigm for cognitive science, ed. J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, and E.A. Di Paolo. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. 2014. The feeling body: Affective science meets the enactive mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G., and E. Thompson. 2008. The feeling body: Toward an enactive approach to emotion. In Developmental perspectives on embodiment and consciousness, ed. W.F. Overton, U. Müller, and J.L. Newman. New York: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A.D. 2002. How do you feel? Interoception: The sense of the physiological condition of the body. Nature Reviews. Neuroscience 3(8): 655–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A.D., and A. Blomqvist. 2002. Is there a specific lamina I spinothalamocortical pathway for pain and temperature sensations in primates? The Journal of Pain 3(2): 95–101. doi:10.1054/jpai.2002.122953.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A.D. 2003a. A new view of pain as a homeostatic emotion. Trends in Neurosciences 26(6): 303–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A.D. 2003b. Interoception: The sense of the physiological condition of the body. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 13(4): 500–505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. 1999. The feeling of what happens: Body and emotion in the making of consciousness. London: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. 2010. Self comes to mind: Constructing the conscious brain. New York: Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desmidt, T., M. Lemoine, C. Belzung, and N. Depraz. 2014. The temporal dynamic of emotional emergence. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13(4): 557–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E.A. 2005. Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4(4): 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E.A. 2009. Extended life. Topoi 28(1): 9–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E.A. 2010. Robotics inspired in the organism. Intellectica 1–2(53–54): 129–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E.A., M. Rohde, and H. De Jaegher. 2010. Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social interaction, and play. In Enaction: Toward a new paradigm for cognitive science, ed. J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, and E.A. Di Paolo. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E., and E. Thompson. 2014. The enactive approach. In The Routledge handbook of embodied cognition, ed. L. Shapiro et al. New York: Routledge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egbert, M.D., X. Barandiaran, and E.A. Di Paolo. 2012. Behavioral metabolution: The adaptive and evolutionary potential of metabolism-based chemotaxis. Artificial Life 18: 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. 2010. From cybernetics to second-order cybernetics: A comparative analysis of their central ideas. Constructivist Foundations 5(2): 75–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. 2012. From adaptive behavior to human cognition: A review of enaction. Adaptive Behavior 20(3): 209–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. 2014. Bio-machine hybrid technology: A theoretical assessment and some suggestions for improved future design. Philosophy & Technology 27(4): 539–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. in press. Life is precious because it is precarious: Individuality, mortality, and the problem of meaning. In Representation and reality: Humans, animals and machines, ed. G. Dodig-Crnkovic and R. Giovagnoli. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., and E.A. Di Paolo. 2011. The enactive approach: Theoretical sketches from cell to society. Pragmatics & Cognition 19(1): 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., and S. Gallagher. 2010. Phenomenology and artificial life: Toward a technological supplementation of phenomenological methodology. Husserl Studies 26(2): 83–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., and J. Stewart. 2010. Life after Ashby: Ultrastability and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Cybernetics & Human Knowing 17(4): 83–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., N. Virgo, and T. Ikegami. 2014. Motility at the origin of life: Its characterization and a model. Artificial Life 20(1): 55–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., and T. Ziemke. 2009. Enactive artificial intelligence: Investigating the systemic organization of life and mind. Artificial Intelligence 173(3–4): 366–500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. 2011. The brain – A mediating organ. Journal of Consciousness Studies 18(7–8): 196–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2005. How the body shapes the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2012. Phenomenology. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2013. The socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research 25–26: 4–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R., and E. Thompson. 2003. The mind-body-body problem. Theoria et Historia Scientarum 7(1): 23–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. [1929] 1995. The fundamental concepts of metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. [1952] 1989. Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. Second Book: Studies in the phenomenology of constitution Trans. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. [1966] 2001. The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kandel, Eric R., James H. Schwartz, and Thomas M. Jessell. 2000. Principles of neural science, 4th ed. New York: McGraw-Hill Medical.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kessel, T. 2011. Phänomenologie des Lebendigen: Heideggers Kritik an den Leitbegriffen der neuzeitlichen Biologie. Freiburg: Karl Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyselo, M. 2014. The body social: An enactive approach to the self. Frontiers in Psychology 5: 986. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00986.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lymer, J. 2011. Merleau-Ponty and the affective maternal-foetal relation. Parrhesia 13: 126–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H.R., and F.J. Varela. 1987. The tree of knowledge: The biological roots of human understanding. Boston: Shambhala Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGregor, S., and N. Virgo. 2011. Life and its close relatives. In Advances in artificial life: 10th European conference, ECAL 2009, ed. G. Kampis, I. Karsai, and E. Szathmáry. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. [1942] 1983. The structure of behavior. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A., and A. Etxeberria. 2005. Agency in natural and artificial systems. Artificial Life 11: 161–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Panksepp, J. 1998. Affective neuroscience: The foundations of human and animal emotions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parisi, D. 2004. Internal robotics. Connection Science 16(4): 325–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plessner, H. [1928] 1975. Die Stufen des Organischen und der Mensch: Einleitung in die philosophische Anthropologie. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V. 2003. On being the object of attention: Implications for self-other consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7(9): 397–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rohde, M., and J. Stewart. 2008. Ascriptional and ‘genuine’ autonomy. BioSystems 91(2): 424–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. [1960] 2004. Critique of dialectical reason. Volume One: Theory of practical ensembles. Trans. A. Sheridan-Smith. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. [1928] 2008. The human place in the cosmos. Trans. M.S. Frings. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherrington, C. 1948. The integrative action of the nervous system. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stapleton, M.L. 2012. Proper embodiment: The role of the body in affect and cognition. PhD dissertation. University of Edinburgh. Retrieved from Edinburgh Research Archive: http://hdl.handle.net/1842/6396.

  • Stapleton, Mog, and Tom, Froese. 2015. Is collective agency a coherent idea? Considerations from the enactive theory of agency. In artificial systems, ed. Catrin Misselhorn, 219–36. Philosophical Studies Series 122. Springer International Publishing, Cham. http://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-3-319-15515-9_12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. 1992. Life = cognition: The epistemological and ontological significance of artificial life. In Toward a practice of autonomous systems: Proceedings of the first European conference on artificial life, ed. F.J. Varela and P. Bourgine. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. 2010. Foundational issues in enaction as a paradigm for cognitive science: From the origin of life to consciousness and writing. In Enaction: Toward a new paradigm for cognitive science, ed. J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, and E.A. Di Paolo. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, A. 1995. Evolving electronic robot controllers that exploit hardware resources. In Advances in artifical life: Third European conference on artificial life, ed. F. Morán, A. Moreno, J.J. Merelo, and P. Chacón. Berlin: Spinger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. 2007. Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. 2011. Reply to commentaries. Journal of Consciousness Studies 18(5–6): 176–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E., and M. Stapleton. 2009. Making sense of sense-making: Reflections on enactive and extended mind theories. Topoi 28(1): 23–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Torrance, S., and T. Froese. 2011. An inter-enactive approach to agency: Participatory sense-making, dynamics, and sociality. Humana. Mente 15: 21–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J. 1979. Principles of biological autonomy. New York: Elsevier North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J. 1991. Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In Organism and the origins of self, ed. A.I. Tauber. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J. 1996. Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies 3(4): 330–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J. 1999. The specious present: A neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science, ed. J. Petitot, F.J. Varela, B. Pachoud, and J.-M. Roy. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J., and N. Depraz. 2005. At the source of time: Valence and the constitutional dynamics of affect. Journal of Consciousness Studies 12(8–10): 61–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J., H.R. Maturana, and R. Uribe. 1974. Autopoiesis: The organization of living systems, its characterization and a model. BioSystems 5: 187–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Uexküll, J. 1909. Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tiere. Berlin: Julius Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Uexküll, J. [1934] 1957. A stroll through the worlds of animals and men: a picture book of invisible worlds. In Instinctive behavior: The development of a Modern Concept, ed. C.H. Schiller. New York: International Universities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., and F.J. Varela. 2002. Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, D., and M. Stapleton. 2012. Es are good: Cognition as enacted, embodied, embedded, affective and extended. In Consciousness in Interaction: The role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousnes, ed. F. Paglieri. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. 2005. Reconstructing the cognitive world the next step. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. 2010. Minds, things and materiality. In The cognitive life of things: Recasting the boundaries of the mind, ed. L. Malafouris and C. Renfrew. Cambridge: McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. 2011. Mind in life or life in mind? Making sense of deep continuity. Journal of Consciousness Studies 18(5–6): 148–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 1999. Self-awareness and alterity: A phenomenological investigation. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 2011. Mutual enlightenment and transcendental thought. Journal of Consciousness Studies 18(5–6): 169–175.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mog Stapleton .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Stapleton, M., Froese, T. (2016). The Enactive Philosophy of Embodiment: From Biological Foundations of Agency to the Phenomenology of Subjectivity. In: García-Valdecasas, M., Murillo, J., Barrett, N. (eds) Biology and Subjectivity. Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30502-8_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics