Skip to main content

A Higher-Order Rejoinder for Reliabilism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Puzzle of Perceptual Justification

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 377))

  • 335 Accesses

Abstract

In the last chapter we saw that process reliabilism was confronted with several problems, at the foremost of which were the lack of a good answer to the New Evil Demon Problem and the Clairvoyance Problem. If reliability is indeed necessary and sufficient for the justification of a specific class of beliefs, then subjects misled by an evil demon are unjustified in their perceptual beliefs, while subjects forming beliefs on the basis of an extravagant but possibly reliable process, such as blindsight or clairvoyance, are justified in their beliefs. Given that we have the intuition that this consequence is false, it seems that process reliabilism must also be false. Process reliabilism is thus in need of a good way to accommodate the New Evil Demon Intuition and the Blindsight (and Clairvoyance) Intuition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Note that Graham (2012, p. 455) also mentions this type of response to the Clairvoyance Problem.

  2. 2.

    The phenomenon of known hallucination might be more difficult to deal with, although it’s not obvious that hallucinatory subjects do not believe that they are perceiving in the relevant sense if they know that they are hallucinating. But note that I am here only presenting a suggestion to the metaphysical question of the phenomenal distinctness of perception; my epistemic position does not commit me to holding that there is a distinctive phenomenal property of experience that has to do with higher-order beliefs.

  3. 3.

    Also see Schwitzgebel (2012) for more on the idea that introspection consists of a plurality of processes, although Schwitzgebel is also notoriously skeptical about the reliability of these processes.

  4. 4.

    Note that Bob Beddor (2015, pp. 155–6) also uses these problems with the availability of alternative cognitive mechanisms to argue against the idea that having such available mechanisms is necessary for defeat.

  5. 5.

    This suggestion is made in slightly different terms of developmentally moderating processes by Bedke (2010, p. 7).

  6. 6.

    Note that this type of defeat clause will also circumvent the counterexample to Bergmann’s theory provided in Johnson (2011), as it only deems the proper functioning of defeater systems relevant if they would have prevented a belief from occurring had they been functioning properly.

  7. 7.

    Colin Ruloff (2000) also argues that an appeal to defeat can protect Plantinga’s proper functionalism from some of BonJour’s counterexamples. However, to account for the precise way in which defeat occurs Ruloff stresses too much (as Plantinga sometimes does (Plantinga 1996, p. 377)) that we already believe that there can be no such thing as clairvoyance. My account is able to explain how defeat arises without supposing that we have any beliefs of this sort.

  8. 8.

    Note that the way in which I propose that defeat occurs for Norman is importantly different from the way in which defeat occurs in BonJour’s other clairvoyant cases (BonJour 1985, pp. 38–40). The other clairvoyants all believe themselves to have a faculty of clairvoyance, even though they all have some evidence that no such faculty is possible or reliable. Norman, in contrast, does not have any evidence of the sort, and also does not believe himself to have a clairvoyant faculty. Yet still his clairvoyant beliefs are defeated, I propose, because of higher-order mechanisms that should have kept him from trusting the ‘strange’ incoming information.

  9. 9.

    Note that his later beliefs will then also become justified, as his monitoring mechanisms would then presumably accept his later beliefs as stemming from a trustworthy source due to their good track record.

  10. 10.

    I limit myself here to a very brief discussion of the distinction between animal and reflective knowledge, although of course much more could be said about Sosa’s theory in general. Note also that Sosa has developed his views further in ways that are not crucial for the current discussion (Sosa 2011, 2015).

  11. 11.

    Note that Greco (2003) also mentions sensitivity to defeating evidence as yet another aspect of cognitive integration. The problem is that he does not explain why Norman, Truetemp, or Norbert would be insensitive to any defeating evidence, a complaint also made by Sven Bernecker (2008).

  12. 12.

    Of course this depends on how the demon is intervening precisely. But I think that the scenario implicitly assumes that the demon is not changing any of the subject’s psychological processes, it’s just stimulating his sensory faculties in a way that is normally done by external stimuli from the world.

  13. 13.

    Note that Graham (2012, p. 455) also mentions that demon victims can provide justifications for their beliefs, but he does not explain how these justifications could depend on further justified beliefs.

  14. 14.

    Internalists that accept this assumption are mentioned in Chaps. 2 and 3, for externalists that accept the assumption see, e.g., Greco (2000), Comesaña (2010), and Goldman (2011b).

  15. 15.

    See the previous chapter, Sect. 5.3.1 for more on this notion of conditional justification.

  16. 16.

    I have presented a way in which higher-order beliefs could influence perceptual phenomenology in Sect. 6.3.1. A more radical position is provided by so-called higher-order theories of consciousness, according to which consciousness has to do with a subject’s higher-order capabilities (e.g., higher-order perception (HOP) of one’s first-order states or higher-order thought (HOT) about one’s first-order states) (Gennaro 2004).

Bibliography

  • Beddor, B. (2015). Process reliabilism’s troubles with defeat. The Philosophical Quarterly, 65(259), 145–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bedke, M. S. (2010). Developmental process reliabilism: On justification, defeat, and evidence. Erkenntnis, 73(1), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J. R. (2004). Reliabilism, truetemp and new perceptual faculties. Synthese, 140(3), 307–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergmann, M. (2006). Justification without awareness: A defense of epistemic externalism. Oxford Scholarship Online. Philosophy module. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bernecker, S. (2008). Agent reliabilism and the problem of clairvoyance. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76(1), 164–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breyer, D., & Greco, J. (2008). Cognitive integration and the ownership of belief: Response to bernecker. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76(1), 173–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2011). The opacity of mind: An integrative theory of self-knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Comesaña, J. (2010). Evidentialist reliabilism. Noûs, 44(4), 571–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dokic, J. (2012). Seeds of self-knowledge: Noetic feelings and metacognition. In M. J. Beran, J. Brandl, J. Perner, & J. Proust (Eds.), Foundations of metacognition (pp. 302–321). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro, R. J. (2004). Higher-order theories of consciousness: An anthology. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge (pp. 1–23). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2011a). Reliabilism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2011 ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/reliabilism/.

  • Goldman, A. (2011b). Toward a synthesis of reliabilism and evidentialism? or: Evidentialism’s troubles, reliabilism’s rescue package. In T. Dougherty (Ed.), Evidentialism and its discontents (pp. 254–280). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2009). Replies to discussants. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 79(1), 245–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, P. J. (2012). Epistemic entitlement. Noûs, 46(3), 449–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, P. J. (2014). Functions, warrant, history. In A. Fairweather & O. Flanagan (Eds.), Naturalizing epistemic virtue (pp. 15–35). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2000). Putting skeptics in their place: The nature of skeptical arguments and their role in philosophical inquiry (2007 digital print ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2003). Further thoughts on agent reliabilism: Replies to cohen, geivett, kvanvig, and schmitt and lahroodi. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(2), 466–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grundmann, T. (2009). Reliabilism and the problem of defeaters. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 79(1), 65–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. (2012). Introspection about phenomenal consciousness: Running the gamut from infallibility to impotence. In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness (pp. 405–422). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Kriegel, U. (2007). Phenomenal epistemology: What is consciousness that we may know it so well? Philosophical Issues, 17(1), 123–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2001). Skepticism and the veil of perception. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, D. M. (2011). Proper function and defeating experiences. Synthese, 182(3), 433–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M., Hashtroudi, S., & Lindsay, D. (1993). Source monitoring. Psychological Bulletin, 114(1), 3–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (2011). On a neglected epistemic virtue. Philosophical Issues, 21(1), 165–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2007). Two approaches to epistemic defeat. In D.-P. Baker (Ed.), Alvin plantinga (pp. 107–124). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (2009). Perception and basic beliefs: Zombies, modules and the problem of the external world. USA: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millar, A. (2010). Knowledge and recognition. In D. Pritchard, A. Millar, & A. Haddock (Eds.), The nature and value of knowledge: Three investigations (pp. 89–188). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper function. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1996). Alvin plantinga replies. In J. Kvanvig (Ed.) Warrant in contemporary epistemology: Essays in honor of Plantinga’s theory of knowledge (pp. 307–378). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (2000). Warranted Christian belief. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ruloff, C. (2000). Some remarks on bonjour on warrant, proper function, and defeasibility. Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology, 4(2), 215–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2012). Introspection, what? In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness (pp. 29–48). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smithies, D. (2012b). A simple theory of introspection. In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness (pp. 259–293). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. I). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2011). Knowing full well. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2015). Judgment and agency. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ghijsen, H. (2016). A Higher-Order Rejoinder for Reliabilism. In: The Puzzle of Perceptual Justification. Synthese Library, vol 377. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30500-4_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics