Skip to main content

Towards a Methodology for Integrated History and Philosophy of Science

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Philosophy of Historical Case Studies

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 319))

Abstract

We respond to two kinds of skepticism about integrated history and philosophy of science: foundational and methodological. Foundational skeptics doubt that the history and the philosophy of science have much to gain from each other in principle. We therefore discuss some of the unique rewards of work at the intersection of the two disciplines. By contrast, methodological skeptics already believe that the two disciplines should be related to each other, but they doubt that this can be done successfully. Their worries are captured by the so-called dilemma of case studies: On one horn of the dilemma, we begin our integrative enterprise with philosophy and proceed from there to history, in which case we may well be selecting our historical cases so as to fit our preconceived philosophical theses. On the other horn, we begin with history and proceed to philosophical reflection, in which case we are prone to unwarranted generalization from particulars. Against worries about selection bias, we argue that we routinely need to make explicit the criteria for choosing particular historical cases to investigate particular philosophical theses. It then becomes possible to ask whether or not the selection criteria were biased. Against worries about unwarranted generalization, we stress the iterative nature of the process by which historical data and philosophical concepts are brought into alignment. The skeptics’ doubts are fueled by an outdated model of outright confirmation versus outright falsification of philosophical concepts. A more appropriate model is one of stepwise and piecemeal improvement.

A glaring asymmetry, obvious at this meeting, is that historians dress better than philosophers – historians always being interested in the details, sartorial and otherwise, while philosophers seem concerned only with dressing in general.

Richards (1992)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Schickore (2011) gives a good overview of the debates about integrated history and philosophy of science since the middle of the 20th century, and she cites many key works. Howard (2011) offers a more long-term history of the relation of the two fields and discusses some of the fundamental reasons for their separation in the 20th century. A good snapshot of the state of the field in the new millennium can be found in Arabatzis and Schickore (2012).

  2. 2.

    While we focus on one flavor of HPS, we see others as complementary and equally valuable. For instance, a key project is to trace the origin and growth of modern concepts, theories and questions (Lennox 2001; Schickore 2011).

  3. 3.

    An indication of this is the tradition of “historical epistemology” (see e.g. Rheinberger 1997; Daston and Galison 2007; and the special issue of Erkenntnis edited by Feest and Sturm 2011).

  4. 4.

    We prefer not to draw a strong distinction between historical and contemporary scientific practice as an object of study. What would have been “contemporary” science to Giere in 1985 is “historical” now, but the theoretical questions we ask about our cases remain largely the same. The only difference are in the methods of study: How recent an episode is will partly dictate whether our tools will include archival studies, oral histories, laboratory notebooks, or questionnaires, not to mention “embedding” oneself in a research group. Depending on method, of course, some questions will be easier to answer than others.

  5. 5.

    Pinnick and Gale (2000) commented that “despite the possibility of doing so, philosophers have not pursued a method of case-study design” (p. 116). They also observed that disciplinary consensus about method coincides with progress.

  6. 6.

    While we adopt Chang’s general framework, we do not think that much hinges on whether we speak of “episodes” or “cases”, and we will continue to use both terms.

  7. 7.

    Schickore (2011) has argued that the history-philosophy relationship should not be understood in terms of a confrontational model, in analogy to the empirical sciences, but in terms of hermeneutics, or “the art of gradually reconciling provisional analytic concepts with a provisional reading of the historical record” (p. 459). However, we believe that the confrontational and the hermeneutic models can be reconciled. Certainly the confrontational model must be conceived, as we discuss, in cyclical and iterative terms. But this is no surprise, since the empirical sciences—on which the confrontational model is based—are similarly iterative in theory testing. Moreover, HPS is in part concerned with the beliefs and desires of human actors, the traditional domain of interpretive, hermeneutic approaches. But this has ample room in the confrontational model, which understands the study of human beliefs and motives in terms of empirical theses about cognitive states (how ever difficult these may be to ascertain).

  8. 8.

    See Scerri (2012) for a critique of Weisberg’s interpretation of Mendeleev’s work.

  9. 9.

    For the time being we refrained from assigning Mendeleev to any of the other subcategories, although Scerri (2012) suggested “classification”—which we should presumably count among theoretical practices.

References

  • Arabatzis, T., and J. Schickore. 2012. Ways of integrating history and philosophy of science. Perspectives on Science 20(4): 395–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. 2006. Discovering cell mechanisms: The creation of modern cell biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. 2010. Eliminative abduction: Examples from medicine. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 41: 345–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burian, R.M. 2001. The dilemma of case studies resolved: The virtues of using case studies in the history and philosophy of science. Perspectives on Science 9(4): 383–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burian, R.M. 2002. Comments on the precarious relationship between history and philosophy of science. Perspectives on Science 10(4): 398–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. 2004. Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. 2011. Beyond case-studies: History as philosophy. In Integrating history and philosophy of science, ed. S. Mauskopf, and T. Schmaltz, 109–124. Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. 2006. Reasoning in biological discoveries. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. 1842. The structure and distribution of coral reefs. London: Smith, Elder and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L., and P. Galison. 2007. Objectivity. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feest, U., and T. Sturm. 2011. What (good) is historical epistemology? Editors’ introduction. Erkenntnis 75(3): 285–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, A., and H. Collins. in press. Two kinds of case study and a new agreement. In The philosophy of historical case studies, boston studies in the philosophy and history of science, ed. T. Sauer, and R. Scholl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.N. 1973. History and philosophy of science: Intimate relationship or marriage of convenience?

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.N. 1985. Philosophy of science naturalized. Philosophy of Science 52(3): 331–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.N. 2011. History and philosophy of science: Thirty-five years later. In Integrating history and philosophy of science, ed. S. Mauskopf, and T. Schmaltz, 59–65. Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. 2005. Hempelian and Kuhnian approaches in the philosophy of medicine: The Semmelweis case. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36(1): 159–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graßhoff, G., and M. May. 1995. Methodische Analyse wissenschaftlichen Entdeckens. Kognitionswissenschaft 5: 51–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N.R. 1962. The irrelevance of history of science to philosophy of science to philosophy of science. The Journal of Philosophy 59(21): 574–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. 1966. Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, D. 2011. Philosophy of science and the history of science. In The continuum companion to the philosophy of science, ed. S. French, and J. Saatsi, 55–71. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. 1992. Testing philosophical claims about science, 468–475. In PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinzel, K. in press. Pluralism in historiography: A case study of case studies. In The philosophy of historical case studies. Boston studies in the philosophy and history of science, ed. T. Sauer, and R. Scholl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L., A. Donovan, R. Laudan, P. Barker, H. Brown, J. Leplin, P. Thagard, and S. Wykstra. 1986. Scientific change: Philosophical models and historical research. Synthese 69(2): 141–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J.G. 2001. History and philosophy of science: A phylogenetic approach. História, Ciências, Saúde-Manguinhos 8(3): 655–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. 2004. Inference to the best explanation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., L. Darden, and C.F. Craver. 2000. Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of science 67(1): 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J.D. 2003. A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science 70(4): 647–670.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orgel, L. 1999. Are you serious, Dr Mitchell? Nature 402(6757): 17–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinnick, C., and G. Gale. 2000. Philosophy of science and history of science: A troubling interaction. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 31(1): 109–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, J.C. 2001. The dilemma of case studies: Toward a heraclitian philosophy of science. Perspectives on Science 9(4): 373–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Räz, T. in press. Gone till november: A disagreement in Einstein scholarship. In The philosophy of historical case studies. Boston studies in the philosophy and history of science, ed. T. Sauer, and R. Scholl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. 1997. Toward a history of epistemic things: Synthesizing proteins in the test tube. California: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R.J. 1992. Arguments in a sartorial mode, or the asymmetries of history and philosophy of science, 482–489. In PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sauer, T., and R. Scholl. in press. Introduction. In The Philosophy of Historical Case Studies. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E.R. 2012. A critique of Weisberg’s view on the periodic table and some speculations on the nature of classifications. Foundations of Chemistry 14(3): 275–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schickore, J. 2011. More thoughts on HPS: Another 20 years later. Perspectives on Science 19(4): 453–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, R. 2013. Causal inference, mechanisms, and the Semmelweis case. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 44(1): 66–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, R., and T. Räz. 2013. Modeling causal structures: Volterra’s struggle and Darwin’s success. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 3(1): 115–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, R., and K. Nickelsen. 2015. Discovery of causal mechanisms: Oxidative phosphorylation and the Calvin-Benson-cycle. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 37(2): 180–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Semmelweis, I.P. 1983. The etiology, concept, and prophylaxis of childbed fever. Trans. K.C. Carter. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, S., and S. Schaffer. 1985. Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, boyle, and the experimental life. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sulloway, F.J. 1982. Darwin’s conversion: The beagle voyage and its aftermath. Journal of the History of Biology 15(3): 325–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulodziecki, D. 2013. Shattering the myth of Semmelweis. Philosophy of Science 80(5): 1065–1075.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Volterra, V. 1926a. Fluctuations in the abundance of a species considered mathematically. Nature 118(2972): 558–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Volterra, V. 1926b. Variazioni e fluttuazioni del numero d’individui in specie animali conviventi. Memorie della R. Accademia dei Lincei 6(2): 31–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Volterra, V. 1928. Variations and fluctuations of the number of individuals in animal species living together. Journal du Conseil/Conseil Permanent International pour l’Exploration de la Mer 3(1): 3–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Volterra, V., and U. D’Ancona. 1935. Les associations biologiques au point de vue mathématique. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. 2007. Who is a modeler? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58(2): 207–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful comments and debates, which have shaped this contribution significantly, we thank first and foremost the participants of the workshop “The philosophy of historical case studies” at the University of Bern (November 21–22, 2013). In addition, we are indebted to Michael Bycroft, Allan Franklin and Jutta Schickore; the participants of the Fifth Conference on Integrated History and Philosophy of Science (&HPS5) at the University of Vienna (June 26–28, 2014); the Visiting and Postdoctoral Fellows at the University of Pittsburgh’s Center for Philosophy of Science (2014–2015); and the members of the Lake Geneva Biology Interest Group (lgBIG). Raphael Scholl was supported by a grant from the Swiss National Science Foundation (grant number P300P1_154590).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Raphael Scholl .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Scholl, R., Räz, T. (2016). Towards a Methodology for Integrated History and Philosophy of Science. In: Sauer, T., Scholl, R. (eds) The Philosophy of Historical Case Studies. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 319. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30229-4_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30229-4_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-30227-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-30229-4

  • eBook Packages: HistoryHistory (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics