Skip to main content

Two Modes of Reasoning with Case Studies

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Philosophy of Historical Case Studies

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 319))

Abstract

I distinguish a predictive and a conceptual mode of reasoning with case studies. These broadly correspond with two different kinds of analogical inference, one relying on common and differing properties, the other on structural similarity. The problem of generalizing from case studies is discussed for both. Regarding the predictive mode, eliminative induction provides a natural framework. In the conceptual mode, general rules are largely lacking not least due to a number of epistemological challenges like Raphael Scholl’s underdetermination problem for HPS. In agreement with ideas of Richard Burian and Peter Galison, I argue that conceptual reasoning on the basis of case studies should not aim at grand universal schemes but rather at mesoscopic or middle-range theory. In the essay, I will repeatedly draw on insights from the social sciences, in which a much more extensive reflection on case study methodology exists compared with HPS.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The term is understood here in a very broad sense, e.g. a historical narrative could also constitute a data structure.

  2. 2.

    A further distinction concerns the type of variation that occurs in a case study (e.g. Gerring 2007, p. 28).

  3. 3.

    See Scholl and Räz , in press (this volume). In the social-science literature, similar classification schemes can be found, e.g. Gerring (2007, pp. 89–90) suggests nine different types of cases: typical, diverse, extreme, deviant, influential, crucial, pathway, most-similar, and most-different.

  4. 4.

    The example was suggested by Raphael Scholl.

  5. 5.

    The term ’eliminative induction’ for Mill’s methods has been used by several authors, in particular by Mill himself (1886, p. 256) and also by Mackie in his influential book The Cement of the Universe. Mackie writes: “In calling them eliminative methods Mill drew a rather forced analogy with the elimination of terms in an algebraic equation. But we can use this name in a different sense: all these methods work by eliminating rival candidates for the role of cause” (Mackie 1980, p. 297).

  6. 6.

    Note that this need not be the case for all properties. For example, if the second man were ill, the probability for his death would presumably increase. This underlines not so much the heuristic nature of analogical inferences but the need for a two-dimensional framework as outlined below.

  7. 7.

    Additional complications may arise in the case of plural causation.

  8. 8.

    “The validity of [an argument by analogy] will depend, first, on the extent of the positive analogy compared with the negative [...] and, second, on the relation between the new property and the properties already known to be parts of the positive or negative analogy, respectively” (Hesse cited in Norton 2011, p. 9).

  9. 9.

    For a good overview from a philosophy-of-science perspective consult Nersessian (2008), who stresses the role of analogy, imagery, and thought experiments. See also Hempel’s (1952) classic treatise on the subject.

  10. 10.

    Galison argues for a “sited, not typical, history”, the aim of which is “to evoke the mesoscopic periods of laboratory history, not a universal method of experimentation” (Galison 1997, p. 63). I largely agree but would add that scientific method nevertheless possesses a universal logical core, which has to be contextualized when analyzing specific episodes.

References

  • Bacon, F. 1994. Novum Organon. Chicago, IL: Open Court (Original edition: London, 1620).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartha, P. 2010. By parallel reasoning: The construction and evaluation of analogical arguments. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bartha, P. 2013. Analogy and analogical reasoning. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/reasoning-analogy.

  • Burian, R. 2001. The dilemma of case studies resolved: The virtues of using case studies in the history and philosophy of science. Perspective on Science 9(4): 383–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. 1980. A basic system of inductive logic. In Studies in inductive logic and probability, ed. R. Jeffrey, 7–155. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. 1983. How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. 2004. Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. 2011. Beyond case-studies: History as philosophy. In Integrating history and philosophy of science: Problems and prospects, ed. S. Mauskopf, and T. Schmaltz, 109–124. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. 1954. The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galison, P. 1997. Image and logic. A material culture of microphysics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • George, A., and A. Bennett. 2005. Case studies and theory development in the social sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerring, J. 2007. Case study research. Principles and practices. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammersley, M., P. Foster, and R. Gromm. 2000. Case study and theory. In Case study method: Key issues, key texts, ed. R. Gromm, M. Hammerseley, and P. Foster, 234–258. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. 1952. Fundamentals of concept formation in empirical science. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. 1966. Philosophy of natural science. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. 1966. Models and analogies in science. Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J.M. 1921. A treatise on probability. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1977. The essential tension. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1992. The Copernican revolution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1996. The structure of scientific revolutions, 3rd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. 1984. Two types of inductive analogy by similarity. Erkenntnis 21: 63–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli, S. 2012. Introduction: data-driven research in the biological and biomedical sciences. Studies in the History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences 43(1–3)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J.L. 1980. The cement of the universe. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. 1949. On sociological theories of the middle range. In Classical sociological theory, ed. C. Calhoun, J. Gerteis, J. Moody, S. Pfaff, and I. Virl, 531–542. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1886. A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive. London: Longmans, Green and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • MMWR. 1981. Pneumocystis Pneumonia-Los Angeles. Morbidity and Mortality Weekly Report 30(21): 1–3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. 2008. Creating scientific concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J.D. 2011. Analogy. Draft chapter of a book on the material theory of induction, http://www.pitt.edu/~jdnorton/papers/material_theory/Analogy.pdf.

  • Pietsch, W. 2014. The nature of causal evidence based on eliminative induction. Topoi 33(2): 421–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pietsch, W. 2015. Aspects of theory-ladenness in data-intensive science. Philosophy of Science 82(5): 905–916.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, J. 2001. The dilemma of case studies: Toward a Heraclitian philosophy of science. Perspective on Science 9(4): 373–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Romeijn, J. 2006. Analogical predictions for explicit similarity. Erkenntnis 64(2): 253–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russo, F., and J. Williamson. 2007. Interpreting causality in the health sciences. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 21(2): 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, R. 2013. Causal inference, mechanisms, and the Semmelweis case. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 44(1): 66–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, R. 2015. Inference to the best explanation in the catch-22: How much autonomy for Mill’s method of difference? European Journal for Philosophy of Science 5(1): 89–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, R., and T. Räz. 2013. Modeling causal structures: Volterra’s struggle and Darwin’s success. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 3(1): 115–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, R., and Räz, T. in press. Towards a methodology for integrated history and philosophy of science. In The philosophy of historical case studies. Boston studies in the philosophy and history of science, ed. T. Sauer, and R. Scholl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, G. 2011. How to do your case study. A guide for students and researchers. Los Angeles: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yin, R. 2009. Case study research, design, and methods. Los Angeles: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am much grateful to the editors of this volume, Tilman Sauer and Raphael Scholl, for helpful comments on the manuscript and also for organizing the inspiring workshop in Bern and contributing so many interesting ideas to the subject themselves. I also thank Christian Joas, Désirée Schauz, and Elsbeth Bösl for helpful discussions as well as Karin Zachmann for pointing me to the insightful discussion by Peter Galison.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wolfgang Pietsch .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Pietsch, W. (2016). Two Modes of Reasoning with Case Studies. In: Sauer, T., Scholl, R. (eds) The Philosophy of Historical Case Studies. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 319. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30229-4_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30229-4_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-30227-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-30229-4

  • eBook Packages: HistoryHistory (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics