Skip to main content

Nudging and the Principle of Proportionality

Obliged to Nudge?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship ((EALELS,volume 3))

Abstract

While the ethics and politics of nudging have received a great deal of attention, the legality of non-coercive interventions aimed at changing human behaviour has not been the object of much study. In this contribution, I examine firstly which limits, if any, the principle of proportionality (‘Verhältnismäßigkeitsgrundsatz’) as applied by the German Federal Constitutional Court imposes on governmental ‘choice architects’. While nudges as such generally do not interfere with fundamental rights, including the very broad ‘right of personal development’ of Art. 2(1) Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany, their implementation will often interfere with the fundamental rights of citizens other than the decision makers and therefore trigger constitutional scrutiny. Since paternalistic motives are – in principle – not accepted as legitimate ends that may justify an interference with fundamental rights, nudges solely intended to protect the decision maker from self-harm may not pass the proportionality test. Secondly, I examine whether the necessity prong of the proportionality principle may force the legislator to choose a non-coercive nudge over a more traditional coercive measure. Given the empirical evidence of the limited effectiveness of nudges in changing behaviour compared to traditional regulatory means, I come to the conclusion that the proportionality principle does not compel the use of nudges.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    An exhaustive overview of the literature is impossible, some starting points are Camerer et al. 2003; Thaler and Sunstein 2003; Rachlinski 2003; Glaeser 2006; Hill 2008; Sugden 2008; Bovens 2009; Hausman and Welch 2010; White 2010; Selinger and Whyte 2011; Blumenthal-Barby and Burroughs 2012; Goodwin 2012; Sunstein 2014; 2015 and the contributions by Bruno S. Frey/Jana Gallus, Peter G. Kirchschläger and Mark D. White in this volume; from a German perspective van Aaken 2006; Schnellenbach 2011; Kirchgässner 2013; Neumann 2013; Fischer and Lotz 2014.

  2. 2.

    But see Alemanno and Spina 2014; van Aaken 2015a, b.

  3. 3.

    Saurer 2012, p. 8; Wahl 2013, p. 823

  4. 4.

    Classen 2012, p. 659; Wahl 2013, p. 836.

  5. 5.

    Pieroth 2014, para. 289; Sodan and Ziekow 2014, p. 227. For an overview over the historic development see Koch 2003, pp. 4 et sq.

  6. 6.

    Tversky and Kahneman 1981.

  7. 7.

    Wansink and van Ittersum 2006.

  8. 8.

    Read and van Leeuwen 1998.

  9. 9.

    E.g., Nessmith et al. 2007; but see Bronchetti et al. 2011; Russell 2015.

  10. 10.

    Johnson and Goldstein 2003.

  11. 11.

    The chapter headings in Pohl 2004 give an overview over the most widely studied fallacies and biases in thinking, judgment and memory.

  12. 12.

    Rachlinski 2003; Englerth 2007, pp. 23 et sq.

  13. 13.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2003, p.175.

  14. 14.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2008, p. 237.

  15. 15.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2008, p. 3.

  16. 16.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2008, p. 6.

  17. 17.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2008, p. 2.

  18. 18.

    Mensink et al. 2003; Micha et al. 2010.

  19. 19.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2008, p. 2.

  20. 20.

    Dayan and Bar-Hillel 2011.

  21. 21.

    Rozin et al. 2011.

  22. 22.

    Since the government is largely free to set contract terms (as long as they are not discriminatory), contracting only with companies that agree to adhere to ‘behavioral food presentation’ may not trigger any constitutional concerns. It is easy to imagine, however, that the government would try to mandate these measures for all restaurants, which would clearly entail coercion.

  23. 23.

    Koch 2003, pp. 39 sq.

  24. 24.

    Koch 2003, pp. 45 sq.

  25. 25.

    Schlink 2001, p. 445.

  26. 26.

    Koch 2003, pp. 48 sqq; Saurer 2012.

  27. 27.

    Arai-Takahashi 2002, pp. 14 sq.

  28. 28.

    See District of Columbia v. Heller, 554 U.S. 570 (2008), for a discussion Cohen-Eliya and Porat 2009; historical overview Porat 2014.

  29. 29.

    E.g. Michael 2001a, p. 148; Stein and Frank 2010, p. 245.

  30. 30.

    E.g. Zippelius and Würtenberger 2008, p. 219; Ipsen 2014, para.184; Sodan and Ziekow 2014, p. 228.

  31. 31.

    See Art. 3(2), 5(2), 8(2), 12(1) Basic Law, and more often. For the understanding of ‘law’ as parliamentary act see Pieroth 2014, paras. 272 et sq.

  32. 32.

    Pieroth 2014, paras. 285 et sq.

  33. 33.

    Peters 1963, pp. 47 et sq.

  34. 34.

    BVerfGE 6, 32, pp. 36 sq. – ‘Elfes decision’.

  35. 35.

    BVerfGE 54, p. 143 – ‘pigeon feeding’; BVerfGE 80, 137, pp. 152 et sq. – ‘riding in the forest’.

  36. 36.

    Ipsen 2014, para. 771; Pieroth 2014, paras. 386 et sq.

  37. 37.

    See the references cited in Cremer 2003, p. 81.

  38. 38.

    Möller 2014, p. 163.

  39. 39.

    Zippelius and Würtenberger 2008, p. 244.

  40. 40.

    Christman 21.3.2015, 1.1 Basic Distinctions.

  41. 41.

    Hill 2008; Sugden 2008; White 2010; Blumenthal-Barby and Burroughs 2012; Goodwin 2012; Miller and Gelinas 2013; Wilkinson 2013; van Aaken 2015b.

  42. 42.

    Christman 21.3.2015, Introduction; cited approvingly by van Aaken 2015b, p. 9.

  43. 43.

    Sunstein 2015, p. 30; van Aaken 2015a, p. 13.

  44. 44.

    BVerfGE 105, 252, p. 268 – ‘glycol warning ’.

  45. 45.

    BVerfGE 105, 252, p. 267 – ‘glycol warning ’.

  46. 46.

    Lüdemann 2004, pp. 123 et sq.

  47. 47.

    Lüdemann 2004, pp. 127 et sq.

  48. 48.

    Blumenthal-Barby 2013, pp. 190 et sqq.; Yeung 2012; Wilkinson 2013.

  49. 49.

    van Aaken 2015b, p. 10; Yeung 2012, p. 138, similarly distinguishes between ‘non-exploitative’ nudges that seek to ensure a rational, informed choice, and ‘expoitative’ nudges that “are designed to alter behaviour by taking advantage of cognitive irrationalities”.

  50. 50.

    van Aaken 2015a, p. 10; 2015b, p. 15.

  51. 51.

    van Aaken 2015a, p. 18; 2015b, p. 14.

  52. 52.

    For an overview see Lichtenstein and Slovic 2006.

  53. 53.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2003, p. 175.

  54. 54.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2008, p. 237.

  55. 55.

    More careful Sunstein 2015, p. 38.

  56. 56.

    Blumenthal-Barby 2013, p. 190.

  57. 57.

    Yeung 2012, p. 134.

  58. 58.

    Kelly 2013, p. 220.

  59. 59.

    van Aaken 2015a, p. 11; 2015b, pp. 13 et sqq.

  60. 60.

    Bateson et al. 2006.

  61. 61.

    As long as it is reasonably easy to opt-out. For a view of default options as effective mandates see Bubb and Pildes 2014, pp. 1616 et sq.

  62. 62.

    For a different view see van Aaken 2015a, p. 10.

  63. 63.

    Castleman et al. 2014.

  64. 64.

    BVerfGE 95, p. 173 – ‘warnings on cigarette packaging’. The plaintiffs also argued that their freedom of speech was affected, the Constitutional Court denied this, id. at 181.

  65. 65.

    Allcott 2011.

  66. 66.

    According to van Boom and Ogus 2010, p. 2. I am not even sure I would call this a nudge at all.

  67. 67.

    Hufen 2014, p. 119; Ipsen 2014, para. 187; unless the fundamental right intefered with is an ‘unconditional’ right (ohne Gesetzesvorbehalt), in which case it may only be intefered with based on competing constitutional right(s), Michael 2001b, p. 655. For a different view see Fischer 1997.

  68. 68.

    e.g., Hufen 2014, p. 119.

  69. 69.

    Instead of many Sodan and Ziekow 2014, p. 229.

  70. 70.

    Dworkin 2013, p. 29.

  71. 71.

    Hillgruber 1992, p. 119; Fischer 1997, p. 273; van Aaken 2006, p. 136. Möller 2005 accepts paternalistic motives as legitimate if the measure is aimed at preserving integrity.

  72. 72.

    The protection from self-harm of people considered incapable of fully using their mind is considered autonomy -preserving, van Aaken 2015b, p. 3. ‘Soft paternalistic’ measures are widely considered legitimate and will not be considered further here.

  73. 73.

    BVerGE 22, 180, pp. 219 et sq. – ‘youth welfare’.

  74. 74.

    Not all nudges are paternalistic, of course. Non-paternalistic nudges will generally pass the legitimate aim prong, van Aaken 2015a, p. 20.

  75. 75.

    Feinberg 1986, pp. 9 et sq.

  76. 76.

    Enderlein 1996, p. 136.

  77. 77.

    van Aaken 2015a, p. 20.

  78. 78.

    BVerfGE 90, 145, p. 172 – ‘cannabis’.

  79. 79.

    In BVerfGe 60, 123, p. 132 – ‘transgender I’, it even held without further elaboration that protection from ‘serious’ self-inflicted harm is a legitimate end.

  80. 80.

    BVerfGE 59, p. 275 – ‘motorcycle helmet’; BVerfG, NJW 1987, p. 180 – ‘seat belt law’.

  81. 81.

    BVerfGE 115, p. 276 – ‘sports betting’.

  82. 82.

    But see Ueltzhöffer 2005, p. 17.

  83. 83.

    BVerfGE 59, p. 275 – ‘motorcycle helmet’.

  84. 84.

    BVerfGE, NJW 1987, p. 180 – ‘seat belt law’.

  85. 85.

    Möller 2005.

  86. 86.

    van Aaken 2015a, p. 21.

  87. 87.

    Art. 437(3) in connection with Art. 474 Bürgerliches Gesetzbuch.

  88. 88.

    Warranty is used in the sense of ‘Gewährleistung’, i.e., the vendor must only warrant that the good was not defective when the risk passed. If the defect occcurs within 6 months after the passing of the risk, it is presumed that it existed when the risk passed, Art. 476 Bürgerliches Gesetzbuch.

  89. 89.

    BVerfGE 81, 242, p. 255 – ‘sales agents’; BVerfGE 89, 214, p. 232 – ‘debt guarantee’.

  90. 90.

    BVerfGE 89, 214, p. 235 – ‘debt guarantee’; BVerfGE NJW 1999, pp. 2749 et sqq.; BVerfGE 60, 329, p. 345 – ‘pension adjustment’.

  91. 91.

    Enderlein 1996, p. 143.

  92. 92.

    See also van Aaken 2015a, p. 21, who considers the Constitutional Court’s jurisprudence ‘evasive’ and ‘less rigorous’ than the doctrine.

  93. 93.

    BVerfGE 115, 267, p. 308 – ‘old debts’.

  94. 94.

    BVerfGE 30, 292, p. 316 – ‘oil reserves’.

  95. 95.

    Michael 2001b, p. 656.

  96. 96.

    BVerfGE 67, 157, p. 175 – ‘surveillance law’. For a critique see Bickenbach 2014, pp. 320 et sq. and the references cited therein.

  97. 97.

    Hufen 2014, p. 119.

  98. 98.

    BVerfGE 67, 157, p. 176 – ‘surveillance law’.

  99. 99.

    BVerfGE 53, 135, p. 145 – ‘chocolate easter bunny’; Sodan and Ziekow 2014, p. 230.

  100. 100.

    Schlink 2001, p. 458, argues that the burden of proof that the measure is required lies with the state, therefore, if there remain doubts, the measure is not justified.

  101. 101.

    Michael 2001b, pp. 656 et sqq.

  102. 102.

    Michael 2001b, p. 657 and Michael and Morlok 2014, p. 308.

  103. 103.

    Michael and Morlok 2014, para. 620.

  104. 104.

    Health warnings on cigarette packaging may be covered by special sleeves, thereby preventing exposure to the warning . There is no legal way to avoid paying tobacco tax, however. The provision of sleeves by tobacco companies may be illegal, but nobody seems to argue that the end consumer is prohibited from using such sleeves, Wilson et al. 2006.

  105. 105.

    van Aaken 2015b, pp. 31 et sqq.

  106. 106.

    Englerth 2007, p. 239.

  107. 107.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2008, p. 8.

  108. 108.

    Marteau et al. 2011; Rayner and Lang 2011; Salazar 2012; Costa-Font et al. 2014; Bubb and Pildes 2014, pp. 5 et sq.; Russell 2015, pp. 22 et sq.; Ito et al. 2015.

  109. 109.

    House of Lords Science and Technology Select Committee 19.07.2011, see id. Box 7 at para. 5.3 for the role of the Behavioural Insights Team. Today, the Behavioural Insights Team is a private enterprise – partially owned by the UK government – “whose mission is to help organisations in the UK and overseas to apply behavioural insights in support of social purpose goals”, see www.behaviouralinsights.co.uk/about-us (last visited 8 February 2016).

  110. 110.

    See list of witnesses in House of Lords Science and Technology Select Committee 19.07.2011, Appendix 2.

  111. 111.

    House of Lords Science and Technology Select Committee 19.07.2011, Table 1 at para. 2.3.

  112. 112.

    House of Lords Science and Technology Select Committee 19.07.2011, paras. 5.8, 8.14.

  113. 113.

    House of Lords Science and Technology Select Committee 19.07.2011, paras. 5.15, 8.16.

  114. 114.

    Willis 2013, p. 1186, p. 1228.

  115. 115.

    Willis 2013, p. 1161.

  116. 116.

    Willis 2013, p. 1229.

  117. 117.

    Bronchetti et al. 2011.

  118. 118.

    Bubb and Pildes 2014, pp. 1647 et sqq. and more often.

  119. 119.

    Bubb and Pildes 2014, pp. 1596 et sqq.

  120. 120.

    Classen 2012, p. 652; Möller 2014, p. 156.

  121. 121.

    Hufen 2014, p. 121; Sodan and Ziekow 2014, p. 230.

  122. 122.

    BVerfGE 118, 168, p. 195 – ‘basic account data’: “Dieses Gebot verlangt, dass die Schwere des Eingriffs bei einer Gesamtabwägung nicht außer Verhältnis zu dem Gewicht der ihn rechtfertigenden Gründe stehen darf”.

  123. 123.

    BVerfGE 115, 320, pp. 345 et sq. – ‘dragnet search II’.

  124. 124.

    BVerfGE 118, 168, p. 195 – ‘basic account data’.

  125. 125.

    BVerfGE 100, 226, p. 242 – ‘heritage site preservation’.

  126. 126.

    Zippelius and Würtenberger 2008, pp. 124 et sqq.; Ipsen 2014, para. 195; Michael and Morlok 2014, para. 626.

  127. 127.

    Schlink 2001, p. 458.

  128. 128.

    Schlink 2001, pp. 461 et sqq.; Pieroth 2014, para. 303; and the references cited in Saurer 2012, p. 31.

  129. 129.

    Alexy 2003, pp. 783 et sqq.; for an English exposition see Jestaedt 2012, pp. 155 et sqq.

  130. 130.

    Alexy 2003, p. 781, argues that the German constitution, by allowing the inteference with fundamental rights based on parliamentary act, assumes commensurability of rights and public interests. For a more pessimistic view see Endicott 2014.

  131. 131.

    Klement 2008, p. 761.

  132. 132.

    Jestaedt 2012, pp. 164 et sqq.

  133. 133.

    Alexy 2003, p. 773; Wienbracke 2013, p. 153; Michael and Morlok 2014, para. 624.

  134. 134.

    ‘Vorbehaltlose Grundrechte’ in German. In this context this means that the German Constitution does not expressely state that these rights may be abridged by a law, as it does for many fundamental rights.

  135. 135.

    Alexy 2003, pp. 780 et sqq.; Michael and Morlok 2014, para. 624 (p. 310 at the top).

  136. 136.

    Alexy 2003, p. 789.

  137. 137.

    The scope of protection of the ‘Berufsfreiheit’ is far reaching, see Ipsen 2014, paras. 634 et sq.

  138. 138.

    Ipsen 2014, paras. 656 et sq.

  139. 139.

    Payandeh 2011, p. 607 (for inconsistent legislation).

  140. 140.

    BVerfGE 115, 267, p. 310 – ‘sports betting’; BVerfGe 121, 317, pp. 362 et ssq – ‘smoking in bars’.

  141. 141.

    Bumke 2010, pp. 87 et sq.

  142. 142.

    BVerfGe 121, 317, p. 385 – ‘smoking in bars’ (Mansing dissenting).

  143. 143.

    Payandeh 2011, p. 606.

  144. 144.

    BVerfGE 121, 317, pp. 355 et sq. – ‘smoking in bars’.

  145. 145.

    Michael 2008.

  146. 146.

    Michael 2008, p. 878.

  147. 147.

    Petersen 2013.

  148. 148.

    BVerfGE 115, 276, pp. 303 et sqq. – ‘sports betting’.

  149. 149.

    BVerfGE 115, 276, pp. 309 et sqq. – ‘sports betting’.

Bibliography

  • Alemanno, Alberto, and Alessandro Spina. 2014. Nudging legally: On the checks and balances of behavioral regulation. International Journal of Constitutional Law 12(2): 429–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, Robert. 2003. Die Gewichtsformel. In Gedächtnisschrift für Jürgen Sonnenschein. 22. Januar 1938 bis 6. Dezember 2000, ed. Jürgen Sonnenschein, Joachim Jickeli, Peter Kreutz, and Dieter Reuter, 771–792. Berlin: De Gruyter Recht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allcott, Hunt. 2011. Social norms and energy conservation. Journal of Public Economics 95(9–10): 1082–1095.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arai-Takahashi, Yutaka. 2002. The margin of appreciation doctrine and the principle of proportionality in the jurisprudence of the ECHR. Antwerp: Intersentia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, Melissa, Daniel Nettle, and Gilbert Roberts. 2006. Cues of being watched enhance cooperation in a real-world setting. Biology Letters 2(3): 412–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickenbach, Christian. 2014. Die Einschätzungsprärogative des Gesetzgebers. Analyse einer Argumentationsfigur in der (Grundrechts-)Rechtsprechung des Bundesverfassungsgerichts. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenthal-Barby, J.S. 2013. Choice architecture: A mechanism for improving decisions while preserving liberty? In Paternalism. Theory and practice, ed. Christian Coons and Michael Weber, 178–196. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Blumenthal-Barby, J.S., and Hadley Burroughs. 2012. Seeking better health care outcomes: The ethics of using the ‘Nudge’. The American Journal of Bioethics 12(2): 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, Luc. 2009. The ethics of nudge. In Preference change. Approaches from philosophy, economics and psychology, ed. Till Grüne-Yanoff and Sven Ove Hansson, 207–219. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bronchetti, Erin Todd, Thomas S. Dee, David B. Huffman, and Ellen Magenheim. 2011. When a nudge isn’t enough. Defaults and saving among low-income tax filers, NBER Working Paper Series (16887). National Bureau of Economic Research, Cambridge (Mass.), USA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bubb, Ryan, and Richard H. Pildes. 2014. How behavioral economics trims its sails and why. Harvard Law Review 127: 1595–1678.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bumke, Christian. 2010. Die Pflicht zur konsistenten Gesetzgebung. Der Staat 49: 77–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, Colin, Samuel Issacharoff, George Loewenstein, Ted O’Donoghue, and Matthew Rabin. 2003. Regulation for conservatives: Behavioral economics and the case for ‘Asymmetric Paternalism.’ University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 151(3): 1211–1254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castleman, Benjamin L., and Lindsay C. Page. 2014. Summer nudging: Can personalized text messages and peer mentor outreach increase college going among low-income high school graduates? Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 115:144–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christman, John. 2015 March 21. Autonomy in moral and political philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/autonomy-moral.

  • Classen, Claus Dieter. 2012. Das Prinzip der Verhältnismäßigkeit im Spiegel europäischer Rechtsentwicklungen. In Der grundrechtsgeprägte Verfassungsstaat. Festschrift für Klaus Stern zum 80. Geburtstag, ed. Michael Sachs and Helmut Siekmann, 651–667. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen-Eliya, Moshe, and Iddo Porat. 2009. The hidden foreign law debate in Heller: The proportionality approach in American Constitutional Law. San Diego Law Review 46: 367–415.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costa-Font, Joan, David R. Just, Barbara Fasolo, and Nattavudh Powdthavee. 2014. Nudging ourselves? The limits of incentivizing ‘Good Behavior’. Applied Economic Perspectives and Policy 36(1): 1–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cremer, Wolfram. 2003. Freiheitsgrundrechte. Funktionen und Strukturen. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dayan, Eran, and Maya Bar-Hillel. 2011. Nudge to nobesity II: Menu positions influence food orders. Judgment and Decision Making 6(4): 333–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Gerald. 2013. Defining paternalism. In Paternalism. Theory and practice, ed. Christian Coons and Michael Weber, 25–38. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Enderlein, Wolfgang. 1996. Rechtspaternalismus und Vertragsrecht. München: C.H. Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Endicott, Timothy. 2014. Proportionality and incommensurability. In Proportionality and the rule of law. Rights, justification, reasoning, ed. Grant Huscroft, Bradley W. Miller, and Grégoire C.N. Webber, 311–342. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Englerth, Markus. 2007. Vom Wert des Rauchens und der Rückkehr der Idioten – Paternalismus als Antwort auf beschränkte Rationalität? In Recht und Verhalten. Beiträge zu behavorial law and economics, ed. Christoph Engel, Markus Englerth, Jörn Lüdemann, and Indra Spiecker, 231–258. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Joel. 1986. Harm to self. The moral limits of the criminal law. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, Kai. 1997. Die Zulässigkeit aufgedrängten staatlichen Schutzes vor Selbstschädigung. Frankfurt am Main: P. Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, Mira, and Sebastian Lotz. 2014. Ist sanfter Paternalismus ethisch vertretbar? Eine differenzierende Betrachtung aus Sicht der Freiheit. Sozialer Fortschritt 63(3): 52–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glaeser, Edward L. 2006. Paternalism and psychology. Regulation 29(2): 32–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, Tom. 2012. Why we should reject ‘Nudge’. Politics 32(2): 85–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, Daniel M., and Brynn Welch. 2010. Debate: To nudge or not to nudge*. Journal of Political Philosophy 18(1): 123–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, Claire. 2008. Anti-anti-anti paternalism. New York University Journal of Law and Liberty 2: 444–454.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hillgruber, Christian. 1992. Der Schutz des Menschen vor sich selbst. München: F. Vahlen.

    Google Scholar 

  • House of Lords Science and Technology Select Committee. 2011July 19. Behaviour Change. Report. HL Paper 179. London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hufen, Friedhelm. 2014. Staatsrecht. München: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ipsen, Jörn. 2014. Staatsrecht. Neuwied: Luchterhand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ito, Koichiro, Takanori Ida, and Makoto Tanaka. 2015. The persistence of moral suasion and economic incentives. Field experimental evidence from energy demand, NBER Working Paper Series (No. 20910).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jestaedt, Matthias. 2012. The doctrine of balancing – strengths & weaknesses. In Institutionalized reason. The jurisprudence of Robert Alexy, ed. Matthias Klatt, 152–172. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Eric J., and Daniel G. Goldstein. 2003. Do defaults save lives? Science 302: 1338–1339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, Jamie. 2013. Libertarian paternalism, utilitarism, and justice. In Paternalism. Theory and practice, ed. Christian Coons and Michael Weber, 216–230. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, Gerhard. 2013. Sanfter Paternalismus, meritorische Güter, und der normative Individualismus. In Grenzen der Konsumentensouveränität, ed. Martin Held, Gisela Kubon-Gilke, and Richard Sturn, 41–62. Marburg: Metropolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klement, Jan Henrik. 2008. Vom Nutzen einer Theorie, die alles erklärt. Robert Alexys Prinzipientheorie aus der Sicht der Grundrechtsdogmatik. JuristenZeitung: 63(15–16):756–763.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koch, Oliver. 2003. Grundsatz der Verhältnismässigkeit in der Rechtsprechung des Gerichtshofs der europäischen Gemeinschaften. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lichtenstein, Sarah, and Paul Slovic. 2006. The construction of preference. An overview. In The construction of preference, ed. Sarah Lichtenstein and Paul Slovic, 1–40. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lüdemann, Jörn. 2004. Edukatorisches Staatshandeln. Steuerungstheorie und Verfassungsrecht am Beispiel der staatlichen Förderung von Abfallmoral. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marteau, T.M., D. Ogilvie, M. Roland, M. Suhrcke, and M.P. Kelly. 2011. Judging nudging: Can nudging improve population health? BMJ (British Medical Journal) 342: d228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mensink, Ronald P., Peter L. Zock, Arnold D.M. Kester, and Martijn B. Katan. 2003. Effects of dietary fatty acids and carbohydrates on the ratio of serum total to HDL cholesterol and on serum lipids and apolipoproteins: A meta-analysis of 60 controlled trials. The American Journal of Clinical Nutrition 77(5): 1146–1155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Micha, Renata, Sarah K. Wallace, and Dariush Mozaffarian. 2010. Red and processed meat consumption and risk of incident coronary heart disease, stroke, and diabetes mellitus a systematic review and meta-analysis. Circulation 121(21): 2271–2283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michael, Lothar. 2001a. Die drei Argumentationsstrukturen des Grundsatzes der Verhältnismäßigkeit. Zur Dogmatik des Über- und Untermaßverbotes und der Gleichheitssätze. JuS 41(2): 148–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michael, Lothar. 2001b. Grundfälle zur Verhältnismäßigkeit. JuS 41(7): 654–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michael, Lothar. 2008. Folgerichtigkeit als Wettbewerbsgleichheit. Juristenzeitung 63: 875–882.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michael, Lothar, and Martin Morlok. 2014. Grundrechte. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Franklin G., and Luke Gelinas. 2013. Nudging, autonomy, and valid consent: Context matters. The American Journal of Bioethics 13(6): 12–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Möller, Kai. 2005. Paternalismus und Persönlichkeitsrecht. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Möller, Kai. 2014. Proportionality and rights inflation. In Proportionality and the rule of law. Rights, justification, reasoning, ed. Grant Huscroft, Bradley W. Miller, and Grégoire C.N. Webber, 155–172. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nessmith, William E., Stephen P. Utkus, and Jean A. Young. 2007. Measuring the effectiveness of automatic enrollment. Vanguard Center for Retirement Research 31: 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neumann, Robert. 2013. Libertärer Paternalismus. Theorie und Empirie staatlicher Entscheidungsarchitektur. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Payandeh, Mehrdad. 2011. Das Gebot der Folgerichtigkeit: Rationalitätsgewinn oder Irrweg der Grundrechtsdogmatik? Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts 136(4): 578–615.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Hans. 1963. Das Recht auf freie Entfaltung der Persönlichkeit in der höchstrichterlichen Rechtsprechung. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Petersen, Niels. 2013. Gesetzgeberische Inkonsistenz als Beweiszeichen. Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts 138: 108–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pieroth, Bodo. 2014. Grundrechte. Heidelberg/München: Müller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pohl, Rüdiger (ed.). 2004. Cognitive illusions. A handbook on fallacies and biases in thinking, judgement and memory. Hove/New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porat, Iddo. 2014. Mapping the American debate over balancing. In Proportionality and the rule of law. Rights, justification, reasoning, ed. Grant Huscroft, Bradley W. Miller, and Grégoire C.N. Webber, 397–416. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rachlinski, Jeffrey J. 2003. The uncertain psychological case for paternalism. Northwestern University Law Review 97: 1165–1225.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayner, Geof, and Tim Lang. 2011. Is nudge an effective public health strategy to tackle obesity? No. BMJ (British Medical Journal) 342(5): d2177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Read, Daniel, and Barbara van Leeuwen. 1998. Predicting hunger: The effects of appetite and delay on choice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 76(2): 189–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rozin, Paul, Sydney Scott, Megan Dingley, Joanna K. Urbanek, Hong Jiang, and Mark Kaltenbach. 2011. Nudge to nobesity I: Minor changes in accessibility decrease food intake. Judgment and Decision Making 6(4): 323–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Jacob Hale. 2015. The separation of intelligence and control. The retirement savings crisis and the limits of soft paternalism. William & Mary Business Law Review 6: 35–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salazar, Alberto. 2012. Libertarian paternalism and the danger of nudging consumers. King’s Law Journal 23(1): 51–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saurer, Johannes. 2012. Die Globalisierung des Verhältnismässigkeitsgrundsatzes. Staat 51: 3–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlink, Bernhard. 2001. Der Grundsatz der Verhältnismäßigkeit. In Festschrift 50 Jahre Bundesverfassungsgericht. Zweiter Band, ed. Peter Badura and Horst Dreier, 445–465. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnellenbach, Jan. 2011. Wohlwollendes Anschubsen: Was ist mit liberalem Paternalismus zu erreichen und was sind seine Nebenwirkungen? Perspektiven der Wirtschaftspolitik 12(4): 445–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Selinger, Evan, and Kyle Whyte. 2011. Is there a right way to nudge? The practice and ethics of choice architecture. Sociology Compass 5(10): 923–935.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sodan, Helge, and Ziekow. 2014. Grundkurs Öffentliches Recht. Staats- und Verwaltungsrecht. München: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Ekkehart, and Götz Frank. 2010. Staatsrecht. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, Robert. 2008. Why incoherent preferences do not justify paternalism. Constitutional Political Economy 19(3): 226–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 2014. Why nudge?: The politics of libertarian paternalism. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 2015. Nudging and choice architecture: Ethical considerations, Yale Journal on Regulation Forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, Richard H., and Cass R. Sunstein. 2003. Libertarian paternalism. American Economic Review 93(2): 175–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, Richard H., and Cass R. Sunstein. 2008. Nudge. Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1981. The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science 211(4481): 453–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ueltzhöffer, Christian. 2005. Die staatliche Einflussnahme auf den Tabakkonsum von Kindern und Jugendlichen in Deutschland. Wien: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Aaken, Anne. 2006. Begrenzte Rationalität und Paternalismusgefahr. In Paternalismus und Recht. In memoriam Angela Augustin (1968–2004), ed. Michael Anderheiden, Peter Bürkli, Hans Michael Heinig, Stephan Kirste, and Kurt Seelmann, 109–144. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Aaken, Anne. 2015a. Constitutional limits to nudging. A proportionality assessment. University of St. Gallen Law & Economics Working Paper (2015–03): 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Aaken, Anne. 2015b. Judge the nudge. In search of the legal limits of paternalistic nudging in the EU. University of St. Gallen Law & Economics Working Paper (2015–01): 1–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Boom, Willem H., and Anthony Ogus. 2010. Introducing, defining and balancing autonomy v. paternalism. Erasmus Law Review 3: 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wahl, Rainer. 2013. Der Grundsatz der Verhältnismäßigkeit. Ausgangslage und Gegenwartsproblematik. In Verfassungsstaatlichkeit im Wandel. Festschrift für Thomas Würtenberger zum 70. Geburtstag, ed. Dirk Heckmann, Ralf P. Schenke, and Gernot Sydow, 823–854. Berlin: Duncker et Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wansink, Brian, and Koert van Ittersum. 2006. The visual illusions of food: Why plates, bowls, and spoons can bias consumption volume. The FASEB Journal 20(4): A618.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, M.D. 2010. Behavioral law and economics: The assault on consent, will, and dignity. In Essays on philosophy, politics & economics. Integration & common research projects, ed. Christi Favor, Gerald F. Gaus, and Julian Lamont, 201–224. Stanford: Stanford Economics and Finance.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wienbracke, Mike. 2013. Der Verhältnismäßigkeitsgrundsatz. Zeitschrift für das Juristische Studium 2: 148–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, T.M. 2013. Nudging and manipulation. Political Studies 61(2): 341–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Willis, Lauren E. 2013. When nudges fail. Slippery defaults. University of Chicago Law Review 80: 1155–1229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Nick, George Thomson, Philippa Howden-Chapman, and Louise Signal. 2006. Regulations should ban the sale of cigarette pack covers of health warnings. The New Zealand Medical Journal 119(1243): U2251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeung, Karen. 2012. Nudge as fudge. The Modern Law Review 75(1): 122–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zippelius, Reinhold, and Thomas Würtenberger. 2008. Deutsches Staatsrecht. Ein Studienbuch. München: C.H. Beck.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Schweizer .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schweizer, M. (2016). Nudging and the Principle of Proportionality. In: Mathis, K., Tor, A. (eds) Nudging - Possibilities, Limitations and Applications in European Law and Economics. Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-29562-6_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-29562-6_7

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-29560-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-29562-6

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics