Skip to main content

Condorcet’s Jury Theorem as a Rational Justification of Soft Paternalistic Consumer Policies

A Philosophical Note

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Nudging - Possibilities, Limitations and Applications in European Law and Economics

Part of the book series: Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship ((EALELS,volume 3))

Abstract

The aim of this note is to revisit the meaningfulness of the Condorcet Jury Theorem (CJT) and apply it to the recent debate on liberal paternalism and consumer protection. The CJT consists of two parts, (a) stating that a jury of experts is always more competent than a single expert given a certain level of competence, and (b) asserting that for large juries, the collective competence approaches infallibility. This note argues that these insights suggest the application of a Condorcet jury voting procedure in case of nudging boundedly rational consumers. The note proposes a simple calculus for finding an optimal jury size and advocates consumers’ meta-preferences as the jury’s evaluative dimension for designing soft paternalistic policies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Thaler and Shefrin 1981, p. 39.

  2. 2.

    Kahneman 2011.

  3. 3.

    Camerer et al. 2004; Rabin 2002.

  4. 4.

    Armstrong and Vickers 2012.

  5. 5.

    Sunstein and Thaler 2003; Thaler and Sunstein 2003, 2008.

  6. 6.

    Sunstein and Thaler 2003, p. 1190.

  7. 7.

    Glaeser 2006.

  8. 8.

    Rizzo and Whitman 2009; Schnellenbach 2012; Sugden 2008.

  9. 9.

    Kaniovski 2010; Kaniovski and Zaigraev 2011; Peleg and Zamir 2012.

  10. 10.

    Hausman and Welch 2010.

  11. 11.

    Grüne-Yanoff 2009, 2012; Mitchell 2005.

  12. 12.

    Holler 2015.

  13. 13.

    Glaeser 2006; Schnellenbach 2012.

  14. 14.

    Rizzo and Whitman 2009; Schnellenbach 2012; Sugden 2008.

  15. 15.

    Sunstein and Thaler 2003, p. 1162.

  16. 16.

    Sugden 2008.

  17. 17.

    Rizzo and Whitman 2009.

  18. 18.

    Hayek 1945, p. 519.

  19. 19.

    Camerer et al. 2003.

  20. 20.

    See, for one, Grofman and Feld 1988.

  21. 21.

    Sunstein 2014, p. 61.

  22. 22.

    Grofman et al. 1983.

  23. 23.

    Grofman et al. 1983.

  24. 24.

    Kirstein and Wangenheim 2010.

  25. 25.

    Kaniovski 2010. See also Berg 1993, Ladha 1993 or Peleg and Zamir 2012 for an in-depth discussion of the criterion of independence.

  26. 26.

    Berg 1996.

  27. 27.

    Feddersen and Pesendorfer 1998.

  28. 28.

    Grofman et al. 1983; Berg 1996.

  29. 29.

    Guarnaschelli et al. 2000, p. 413.

  30. 30.

    Ladha et al. 1996.

  31. 31.

    Black 1958; Grofman and Feld 1988; List and Goodin 2001; Miller 1986.

  32. 32.

    This idea is based on Calabresi’s seminal work The Costs of Accidents (1970) which deals with efficiency analysis of tort law. Therein, Calabresi argues that the goal of tort law is the minimization of total expected accident costs, which include both the expected costs of the accidents and the spent costs for avoiding the accidents.

  33. 33.

    Sunstein 2015, p. 18.

  34. 34.

    Gigerenzer 2014.

  35. 35.

    Darby 2006.

  36. 36.

    For example in form of the well-known FLO International’s Fairtrade certification.

  37. 37.

    Loureiro and Lotade 2005.

  38. 38.

    The individual with “complete information , unlimited cognitive abilities, and no lack of willpower” is the normative benchmark individual for Thaler and Sunstein 2003, p. 176.

  39. 39.

    Frankfurt 1971; Thaler and Shefrin 1981.

  40. 40.

    Thaler and Shefrin 1981, p. 39.

  41. 41.

    Kahneman 2011.

  42. 42.

    Strack and Deutsch 2004.

  43. 43.

    Mueller et al. 2010.

  44. 44.

    On the importance of pleasure, see Dolan 2014.

  45. 45.

    Schnellenbach 2012.

  46. 46.

    Mueller et al. 2010. Sunstein 2015.

  47. 47.

    Sunstein 2015.

  48. 48.

    Kirchgässner 2014, p. 15.

  49. 49.

    Kirchgässner 2013.

  50. 50.

    For empirical arguments backing the existence of stable long-term preferences , see: Kahneman 2003, or Strack and Deutsch 2004.

  51. 51.

    For an in-depth discussion on how to identify meta-preferences, see Beshears et al. (2008). The authors identify six approaches that jointly contribute to the identification of, what they call, normative preferences: structural estimation, active decisions, asymptotic choice, aggregated revealed preferences, reported preferences and informed preferences.

  52. 52.

    Camerer et al. 2003; Thaler and Sunstein 2008.

  53. 53.

    Fehr and Singer 2005; Singer and Hein 2012.

  54. 54.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2003, 2008.

  55. 55.

    Kaniovski 2010.

  56. 56.

    Holler and Leroch 2010.

  57. 57.

    See also Sunstein 1999.

  58. 58.

    Guarnaschelli et al. 2000; Ladha 1996.

  59. 59.

    Brock 2011.

  60. 60.

    Marteau et al. 2011.

  61. 61.

    WHO 2008; Willis 2011.

  62. 62.

    Jolls 2013.

  63. 63.

    Johnson et al. 2002.

  64. 64.

    Armstrong and Vickers 2012.

  65. 65.

    Dold and Holler 2015.

Bibliography

  • Armstrong, Mark, and John Vickers. 2012. Consumer protection and contingent charges. Journal of Economic Literature 50(2): 477–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg, Sven. 1993. Condorcet’s jury theorem, dependency among jurors. Social Choice and Welfare 10(1): 87–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg, Sven. 1996. Condorcet’s jury theorem and the reliability of majority voting. Group Decision and Negotiation 5(3): 229–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beshears, John, James J. Choi, David Laibson, and Brigitte C. Madrian. 2008. How are preferences revealed. Journal of Public Economics 92(8): 1787–1794.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, Duncan. 1958. The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brock, J. Michelle, Andreas Lange, and Y. Ozbay Erkut. 2011. Dictating the risk -experimental evidence on giving in risky environments. Working papers 139, European Bank for Reconstruction and Development.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calabresi, Guido. 1970. The cost of accidents: A legal and economic analysis. Yale: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, Colin, Samuel Issacharoff, George Loewenstein, Ted O’Donoghue, and Matthew Rabin. 2003. Regulation for conservatives: Behavioural economics and the case for ‘asymmetric paternalism’. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 151: 1211–1254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, Colin, George Loewenstein, and Matthew Rabin. 2004. Behavioural economics: Past, present, future. In Advances in behavioural economics, ed. C.F. Camerer, G. Loewenstein, and M. Rabin, 3–51. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Condorcet, Marquis de. 1785. Essai sur l’application de l’analyse a la probability des decisions rendues a la plurality des voix. Paris: De l’imprimerie royale. Translated in 1976 to ‘Essay on the Application of Mathematics to the Theory of Decision-Making’. In Condorcet: Selected Writings, ed. K. M. Baker. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merril.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darby, Sarah. 2006. The effectiveness of feedback on energy consumption. A Review for DEFRA of the Literature on Metering, Billing and direct Displays 486.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dolan, Paul. 2014. Happiness by design: Change what you do, not how you think. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dold, Malte, and Manfred J. Holler. 2015. Nudging, responsibility, and the Condorcet paradox (paper in progress).

    Google Scholar 

  • Feddersen, Timothy, and Wolfgang Pesendorfer. 1998. Convicting the innocent: The inferiority of unanimous jury verdicts under strategic voting. American Political Science Review 92: 23–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, Ernst, and Tanja Singer. 2005. The neuroeconomics of mind reading and empathy. American Economic Review, AEA Papers and Proceedings 95(2):340–345.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H.G. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy 68: 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, Gerd. 2014. Risk savvy: How to make good decisions. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glaeser, Edward L. 2006. Paternalism and psychology. University of Chicago Law Review 73: 133–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grofman, Bernard, and Scott L. Feld. 1988. Rousseaus general will: A condorcetian perspective. The American Political Science Review 82(2): 567–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grofman, Bernard, Guillermo Owen, and Scott L. Feld. 1983. Thirteen theorems in search of the truth. Theory and Decision 15: 261–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, Till. 2009. Welfare notions for soft paternalism, Papers on economics and evolution, vol. 0917. Jena: Evolutionary Economics Group, MPI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, Till. 2012. Old wine in new casks: Libertarian paternalism still violates liberal principles. Social Choice and Welfare 38: 635–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guarnaschelli, Serena, Richard D. McKelvey, and Thomas R. Palfrey. 2000. An experimental study of jury decision rules. American Political Science Review 94: 407–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, Daniel M., and Brynn Welch. 2010. Debate: To nudge or not to nudge. Journal of Political Philosophy 18(1): 123–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, Friedrich A. 1945. The use of knowledge in society. American Economic Review 35: 519–530.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holler, M.J., and M.A. Leroch. 2010. Jury on stage: A common law play. European Journal of Law and Economics 30(2): 89–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holler, Manfred J. 2015. Paternalism, gamification, or art: An introductory note. Homo Oeconomicus 32(2). (forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Eric J., Steven Bellman, and Gerald L. Lohse. 2002. Defaults, framing and privacy: Why opting in-opting out. Marketing Letters 13(1): 5–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jolls, Christine. 2013. Product warnings, debiasing, and free speech: The case of tobacco regulation. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 169(1): 53–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel. 2003. Maps of bounded rationality: Psychology for behavioural economics. The American Economic Review 93(5): 1449–1475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel. 2011. Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaniovski, Serguei. 2010. Aggregation of correlated votes and Condorcet’s jury theorem. Theory and Decision 69(3): 453–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaniovski, Serguei, and Alexander Zaigraev. 2011. Optimal jury design for homogeneous juries with correlated votes. Theory and Decision 71(4): 439–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, Gebhard. 2013. Sanfter Paternalismus, meritorische Güter und der normative Individualismus. In Grundfragen der Ökonomik: Grenzen der Konsumentensouveränität, ed. M. Held, G. Kubon-Gilke, and R. Sturn, 41–62. Marburg: Metropolis-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, Gebhard. 2014. Soft paternalism, merit goods, and normative individualism. CESifo working paper no. 4688.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirstein, Roland, and Georg von Wangenheim. 2010. A generalized Condorcet jury theorem with two independent probabilities of error (No. 11-2010). Joint discussion paper series in economics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladha, Krishna K. 1993. Condorcet’s jury theorem in light of de Finetti’s theorem: Majority-rule voting with -correlated votes. Social Choice and Welfare 10: 69–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladha, Krishna K., Gary J. Miller, and Joe Oppenheimer. 1996. Information aggregation by majority rule: Theory and experiments. Mimeo, University of Maryland.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, Christian, and Robert E. Goodin. 2001. Epistemic democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet jury theorem. Journal of Political Philosophy 9(3): 277–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loureiro, Maria L., and Justus Lotade. 2005. Do fair trade and eco-labels in coffee wake up the consumer conscience? Ecological Economics 53(1): 129–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marteau, Theresa M., David Ogilvie, Martin Roland, Marc Suhrcke, and Michael P. Kelly. 2011. Judging nudging: Can nudging improve population health? BMJ 342: 263–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Nicholas R. 1986. Information, electorates, and democracy: Some extensions and interpretations of the Condorcet jury theorem. In Information pooling and group decision making, ed. B. Grofman and G. Owen, 173–192. Greenwich: JAI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Greogory. 2005. Libertarian paternalism is an oxymoron. Northwestern University Law Review 99(3): 1245–1277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mueller, Astrid, James E. Mitchell, Ross D. Crosby, Olaf Gefeller, Ronald J. Faber, Alexandra Martin, and Martina de Zwaan. 2010. Estimated prevalence of compulsive buying in Germany and its association with sociodemographic characteristics and depressive symptoms. Psychiatry Research 180(2): 137–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peleg, Bezalel, and Shmuel Zamir. 2012. Extending the Condorcet jury theorem to a general dependent jury. Social Choice and Welfare 39(1): 91–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, Matthew. 2002. A perspective on psychology and economics. European Economic Review 46: 657–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzo, Mario J. and Douglas G. Whitman. 2009. The knowledge problem of the new paternalism. Brigham Young University Law Review 905: 103–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnellenbach, Jan. 2012. Nudges and norms: On the political economy of soft paternalism. European Journal of Political Economy 28(2): 266–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, Tania, and Grit Hein. 2012. Human empathy through the lens of psychology and social neuroscience. In The primate mind: Built to connect with other minds, ed. F.B.M. de Waal and P.F. Ferrari, 158–174. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strack, Fritz, and Roland Deutsch. 2004. Reflective and impulsive determinants of social behaviour. Personality and Social Psychology Review 8(3): 220–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, Robert. 2008. Why incoherent preferences do not justify paternalism. Constitutional Political Economy 19(3): 226–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 1999. The law of group polarization. University of Chicago: John M. Ohlin Law & Economics Working Paper No. 91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 2014. Why nudge? The politics of libertarian paternalism. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 2015. Nudging and choice architecture: Ethical considerations. Yale Journal on Regulation, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R., and Richard H. Thaler. 2003. Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. The University of Chicago Law Review 70(4): 1159–1202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, Richard H., and Hersh M. Shefrin. 1981. An economic theory of self-control. The Journal of Political Economy 89: 392–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, Richard H., and Cass R. Sunstein. 2003. Libertarian paternalism. American Economic Review 93(2): 175–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, Richard H., and Cass R. Sunstein. 2008. Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • WHO. 2008. Behaviour change strategies and health: the role of health systems. Regional Committee for Europe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willis, Lauren E. 2011. The financial education fallacy. The American Economic Review 101: 429–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

I thank Manfred J. Holler for an in-depth discussion on the draft of the paper and I am grateful for the valuable comments of Christian Schubert, Jan Schnellenbach and the participants of the 4th Law and Economics Conference in Lucerne on Nudging . All errors, of course, remain mine.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Malte Frederic Dold M.A. .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Dold, M.F. (2016). Condorcet’s Jury Theorem as a Rational Justification of Soft Paternalistic Consumer Policies. In: Mathis, K., Tor, A. (eds) Nudging - Possibilities, Limitations and Applications in European Law and Economics. Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-29562-6_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-29562-6_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-29560-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-29562-6

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics