Skip to main content

The Game of Complexity and Linguistic Theorization

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Language in Complexity

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Morphogenesis ((LECTMORPH))

Abstract

Articulating simplicity and complexity is fundamental for any knowledge endeavor. This chapter carries a critical examination of several possible options in linguistics. Starting with the ancient debate between analogist and anomalist grammar schools, we address the following issues: the nomothetic approach as a reduction to simplicity, and research of determinant laws; complexity, replayed in the models of Complex Systems; the notion of emergence, between determinant and reflective judgment; the assessment of Complex Systems as an apparent middle path to Semiolinguistics; a discussion of linguistic theories directly concerned with the issues of meaning and complexity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Separation redistributed by Kant through the relation between intuition and understanding.

  2. 2.

    But «Varro excellently reminds that it was by borrowing from mathematicians their proportional relationship (analogon, in Greek) that the Alexandrian grammarians were the first to be able to clearly establish, in the form of tables, the complex paradigms of Greek flexional morphology» [translation], op. cit. p. 8.

  3. 3.

    Regarding this too hastily reconstituted debate, one could think that it is a matter of a bipolarity of the regular/monstrous or regular/pathological type, but in truth, it is an indefinite variety of forms exceeding any typology which should be put forth here—and, in parallel, the idea of regularity should be made compatible with that of indetermination—but this is a much more contemporary reformulation.

  4. 4.

    Let us emphasize in passing that the mathematical or logical/computer-scientific schemes in question were not themselves bearers of the epistemologies or of the ideologies that they may have contributed in founding. Even if, initially, the logico-mathematical schemes could appear as univocal epistemological emblems, nothing would prevent them from ulteriorly being requalified and put in the service of a plurality of epistemologies. Hence, the existence of computers and of programming languages by no means requires a logical and computational conception of the mind and of language. We may just as well consider this as an avatar of writing, having a form of hybridization with the idea of mechanism. Thus, a contrario, computer science has given rise to an unprecedented proliferation of diagrams and images which have contributed to the development of topological, dynamic and genetic conceptions, initially undervalued to the benefit of a purely computational vision.

  5. 5.

    The irony of this being that in order to establish its own autonomy, each component of the global architecture (each subdiscipline) recommends its own criteria and a very specific level of objectivity. But then, the encounter between the different levels believed to be separable becomes problematic. The strategy of enunciative linguistics, for example, was to refuse such a separation: without renouncing the idea of a core of meaning, nor that of tiered layers, they are conceived differently, within an apparatus which anticipates beforehand the linguistic value of the enunciative and pragmatic activity.

  6. 6.

    All being ingredients proposed at times by favoring relationships over elements, at other times by conferring these a first form of individuation which then supports relational connections specifying their identity.

  7. 7.

    And this even if, for us, in the contemporary context, it would be suitable for such linguistics to invoke yet a different type of knowledge, left uncovered by the system of the three Critiques, and consisting in the exposition of a reasoned distribution of competing interpretive points of view regarding a same value-form.

  8. 8.

    This temporal parameter t is in fact far from referring to a clearly identifiable time. It is better conceived as a parameter controlling the system’s variations in state, the progressive interaction of the organization factors retained in the modelization. It is also in correspondence with the time (endowed with an elementary increment value) of the algorithmic process which accomplishes it.

  9. 9.

    By decomposition and synthesis, it is a biophysical framework; by diffusion, transformation, institution, it is a socio-symbolical framework.

  10. 10.

    We can thus evoke the proximity, once observed, between Californian cognitive linguistics and connectionist modelization. In a way, connectionist modelizations in the tradition of PDP (Rumelhart and McClelland 1986) will have reproduced the ambiguities and limits of the cognitive linguistics from which they drew inspiration. Giving preeminence to perceptual-type mechanisms, they conceived of them according to a mentalist and representationalist mode, and since it is a matter of language, they will not have succeeded in dissociating themselves from the traditional schemas of a sentence-based grammar.

  11. 11.

    The notion of value is understood here in the broad sense encompassing all issues at stake in the interactions, be they internal or external, which constitute and are created by the life of systems.

  12. 12.

    As evoked by the title of the pioneering work by H. Atlan Between crystal and smoke [Entre le cristal et la fumée, 1979].

  13. 13.

    It is these schemas of understanding and figuration (in torrents, populations, forms, metamorphoses) which then occupy the center of the reconstructions, instead of the ideas of writing and of rewriting which represent another vision of temporality, in thought and in history (theme noted by the philosopher C. Malabou).

  14. 14.

    Cf. a contrario the propositions developed in (Cadiot and Visetti 2001, Visetti and Cadiot 2006) where it was a question, through a discussion with various linguistic theories including Interpretive Semantics, of rethinking the semiolinguistic field in dynamicist terms, as a deployment of forms participating in several regimes or phases of meaning, each referring to a certain mode of linguistic genericity. We then call “motifs” the semantic formations which carry a genericity, said to be figural, that is characteristic of instable phases, and possibly present under various textual formants (e.g. morphemes, lexemes, idiomatic expressions, isotopies, etc.).

  15. 15.

    Thus, the term “seme” does not appear in the preface to the 3rd edition of the theory’s founding work.

  16. 16.

    Thus, the first of these epistemological orientations seems to allow for the designations or glosses of semes to have only a conventional status (albeit motivated since it deals with lexicalization), whereas the semes are conceived as “method invariants”, which their name may indicate but does not constitute. In the second orientation, on the other hand, it is not so directly a question of “method”, and we would expect the more opportunistic nature of the seme, which is then to be understood as an event within a trajectory (an “interpretive moment”), to result in a particular concern for its designation. But such is not the case. And when it does appear to be so, it is simply that the analytical notion of semic relation has been substituted with the more simply empirical notion of co-occurrence.

  17. 17.

    Including a distancing from CT, which however remains a foundational moment, for each one of us, in our progressions steered towards different horizons.

  18. 18.

    Also, cf. the works of the two authors cited in the bibliography.

References

  • Cadiot, P., & Visetti, Y.-M. (2001). Pour une théorie des formes sémantiques—motifs, profils, thèmes. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coseriu, E. (1958/2007). Synchronie, diachronie et histoire, Traduction par T. Verjans de Sincronia, diacronìa e historia. El problema del cambio linguistico (1958). Texte français intégral disponible sur http://www.revue-texto.net/Parutions/Parutions.html.

  • Culioli, A. (1990). Pour une linguistique de l’énonciation. Opérations et représentations, T. 1. Paris: Ophrys.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dessalles, J.-L. (2000). Aux origines du langage. Une histoire naturelle de la parole. Paris: Hermès-Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douay, F., & Pinto, J.-J. (1991). Analogie/anomalie. Persée, 53(1), 7–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupuy, J.-P. (1994). Aux origines des sciences cognitives. Paris: La Découverte.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, M. (1975). Méthodes en syntaxe, Hermann,

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, Z. (1960). Structural linguistics. Chicago: University Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langacker, R. (1987). Foundations of cognitive grammar. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, J. (1992). Physique du sens: de la théorie des singularités aux structures sémio-narratives. Paris: Éditions du CNRS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, J., & Doursat, R. (2011). Cognitive morphodynamics: Dynamical morphological models for constituency in perception and syntax. Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piotrowski, D. (1997). Dynamiques et Structures en Langue. Éditions du CNRS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piotrowski, D. (2009). Phénoménalité et Objectivité Linguistiques. Champion: Collection Bibliothèque de Grammaire et de Linguistique.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piotrowski, D. (2010). Morphodynamique du signe; I—L’architecture fonctionnelle. Cahiers Ferdinand de Saussure, 63, 185–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piotrowski, D. (2011). Morphodynamique du signe; II—Retour sur quelques concepts saussuriens. Cahiers Ferdinand de Saussure, 64, 101–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piotrowski, D. (2013). L’opposition sémiotique/sémantique comme articulation de la conscience verbale. Versus, 117, 27–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piotrowski, D., & Visetti, Y.-M. (2014). Connaissance sémiotique et mathématisation, sémiogenèse et explicitation. Versus, 118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ploux, S., & Victorri, B. (1998). Construction d’espaces sémantiques à l’aide de dictionnaires de synonymes. Traitement automatique des langues, 39(1), 161–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rastier, F. (1987). Sémantique interprétative. Paris: PUF, coll. Formes sémiotiques.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rastier, F. (1997). Meaning and textuality. University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rastier, F., & Valette, M. (2009) De la polysémie à la néosémie. La problématique du mot, S. Mejri, éd., Le français moderne, 77, 97–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regier, T. (1996). The human semantic potential: Spatial language and constrained connectionism. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, D., & McClelland, J. (Eds.). (1986). Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, J. (2004). Trust the text: Language corpus and discourse. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolensky, P., & Legendre, G. (2006). The harmonic mind: From neural computation to optimality-theoretic grammar (Vols. 1 and 2). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmy, L. (2000). Towards a cognitive semantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thom, R. (1972). Stabilité structurelle et morphogenèse. Paris: Édiscience.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Visetti, Y. -M. (2004a). Le Continu en sémantique—une question de Formes. Cahiers de praxématique, 42, numéro coordonné par D. Ablali and M. Valette sur Le Continu : du son au sens, pp. 39–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Visetti, Y. -M. (2004b). Constructivismes, émergences : une analyse sémantique et thématique. Intellectica, 2004/2, 39, 229–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Visetti, Y.-M. (2004c). Language, space and theory of semantic forms. In A. Carsetti (Ed.), Seeing, thinking and knowing—meaning and self-organization in vision and thought (pp. 245–275). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Visetti, Y.-M., & Cadiot, P. (2006). Motifs et proverbes—Essai de sémantique proverbiale. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Piotrowski .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Piotrowski, D., Visetti, YM. (2017). The Game of Complexity and Linguistic Theorization. In: La Mantia, F., Licata, I., Perconti, P. (eds) Language in Complexity. Lecture Notes in Morphogenesis. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-29483-4_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-29483-4_1

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-29481-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-29483-4

  • eBook Packages: EngineeringEngineering (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics