Skip to main content

Manipulating Sources of Information: Towards an Interpretation of Linear Logic and Strong Relevance Logic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
J. Michael Dunn on Information Based Logics

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 8))

Abstract

Relevance Logics are interpreted in terms of agents’ comprehending and constructing sources of information. The rules governing these constructions are formulated in a natural deduction system. Two different sorts of interpretation are developed. On the productive interpretation, implications keep track of the number of times sources are to be applied to one another to produce a particular result. On the functional interpretation, only what is doable in principle (with whatever number of applications) is represented. The productive interpretation is used to understand the contraction-free logics, linear logic and RW. The functional approach is used to understand the logics LR and R.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Perhaps the “opinion tetrahedron” that Dunn (2010) sets out can be extended to treat the full vocabulary of relevance logic, including the intensional connectives. At any rate, I do not know how to do that at this time. My only point here is to support a strong distinction between sources and their contents and the topic of uncertainty and risk helps to do that.

  2. 2.

    See Sect. 12 for more discussion of the denotation of sources. The issue is similar to the relationship between relevance subscripts in the Anderson–Belnap natural deduction system and indices in the Routley–Meyer semantics. A set of numerals \(\alpha \) picks out a collection of indices that are related to those denoted by the numerals in \(\alpha \).

  3. 3.

    There are other ways of generating the distribution rule than this. Anderson and Belnap add a primitive rule. Ross Brady adopts a structural connective that corresponds in some sense to extensional disjunction. Dunn incorporates the mechanism that is found in his and Mints’ sequent systems of having conjunctive hypotheses (Dunn and Restall 2002, Sect. 1.5). Dunn’s proposal is particularly interesting and it might be illuminating to provide a source of information reading of it.

  4. 4.

    The semantics for linear logic created by Allwein and Dunn (1993) might also be a candidate for a source reading, but I do not have the room here to discuss its complexities.

References

  • Allwein, G., & Dunn, J. M. (1993). Kripke semantics for linear logic. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 58(2), 514–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, A. R., & Belnap, N. D. (1975). Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity (Vol. I). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, A. R., Belnap, N. D., & Dunn, J. M. (1992). Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity (Vol. II). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker-Finch, C., (1992). Relevant logic and strictness analysis (pp. 81–82). LaBRI, Bordeaux, Bigre: Workshop on Static Analysis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J., & Restall, G. (2006). Logical pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N. (1993). Life in the undistributed middle. In K. Došen & P. Schröder-Heister (Eds.), Substructural Logics (pp. 31–41). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bimbó, K. (1999). Substructural Logics, Combinatory Logic, and \(\lambda \)-calculus, PhD thesis, Indiana University, Bloomington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bimbó, K. (2004). Semantics for dual and symmetric combinatory calculi. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 33, 125–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunder, M. (2003). Intersection type systems and logics related to the Routley-Meyer system B\(^+\). Australasian Journal of Logic, 1, 43–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dezani-Ciancaglini, M., Meyer, R. K., & Motohama, Y. (2002). The semantics of entailment omega. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 43, 129–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1966). The Algebra of Intensional Logics, PhD thesis, University of Pittsburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1968). Natural versus formal languages. Given at an American Philosophical Association meeting.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1976). Intuitive semantics for first-degree entailments and ‘coupled trees’. Philosophical Studies, 29, 149–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1987). Relevant predication 1: The formal theory. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 16, 347–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1990a). Relevant predication 2: Intrinsic properties and internal relations. Philosophical Studies, 60, 177–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1990b). Relevant predication 3: Essential properties. In J. M. Dunn & A. Gupta (Eds.), Truth or Consequences: Essays in Honour of Nuel Belnap (pp. 77–95). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1993). Star and perp: Two treatments of negation. Philosophical Perspectives, 7, 331–357. (Language and Logic, J. E. Tomberlin (ed.)).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (2010). Inconsistent information: Too much of a good thing. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 39, 425–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M., & Meyer, R. K. (1997). Combinators and structurally free logic. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 5, 505–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M., & Restall, G. (2002). Relevance logic. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic (2nd ed., Vol. 6, pp. 1–128). Amsterdam: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1974). Models for entailment. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 3, 347–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1984). Thoughts. In B. McGuinness (Ed.), Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy (pp. 351–372), Oxford: Blackwell. Originally published in 1918–1919.

    Google Scholar 

  • Girard, J.-Y. (1998). Light linear logic. Information and Computation, 143, 175–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, N., & Mares, E. (2004). CHR: A constructive relevant natural deduction logic. Electronic Notes on Theoretical Computer Science, 91, 158–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E. (2004). Relevant logic: A philosophical interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E. (2009). General information in relevant logic. Synthese, 167, 343–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E. (2010). The nature of information: A relevant approach. Synthese, 175(supplement 1), 111–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ono, H. (1993). Semantics for substructural logics. In K. Došen & P. Schröder-Heister (Eds.), Substructural Logics (pp. 259–291). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz, D. (2006). Natural deduction: A proof-theoretic study. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, S. (1988). Relevant logic: The philosophical interpretation of inference. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slaney, J. (1990). A general logic. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 68, 74–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thistlewaite, P., McRobbie, M., & Meyer, R. K. (1987). Automated theorem proving in non-classical logic. London: Pitman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Troelstra, A. S. (1992). Lectures on linear logic. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urquhart, A. (1972). Semantics for relevance logics. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 37, 159–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yap, A. (2014). Idealization, epistemic logic, and epistemology. Synthese, 191, 3351–3366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I presented a very early draft of this paper to the Pukeko Logic Group. I am grateful to Jeremy Seligman, Zach Weber, and Patrick Girard for their helpful comments. I am also grateful for the two anonymous referees’ helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Edwin Mares .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mares, E. (2016). Manipulating Sources of Information: Towards an Interpretation of Linear Logic and Strong Relevance Logic. In: Bimbó, K. (eds) J. Michael Dunn on Information Based Logics. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 8. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-29300-4_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics