Skip to main content

Biological Organization and Pathology: Three Views on the Normativity of Medicine

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Naturalism in the Philosophy of Health

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL))

Abstract

Medical knowledge aims to identify different diseases as wrong conditions of biological organization. One main issue within the field of the philosophy of medicine is the question of just how confident we can be that what we know about biological organization will help us to identify diseases and propose cures or treatments for them. The concept of biological organization is a complex abstraction which requires the coexistence of constitutive, interactive and experiential aspects; while the main attempts at naturalist descriptions of the concept (functional, mechanistic and systemic) fail to be fully comprehensive. Different arguments have supported a naturalist normativity in medicine; the strongest such perspective contrasts the normal or typical state of organizational elements with their “broken” versions. However, the complexity of biological organization suggests that there are multiple ways of being healthy or diseased. Thus, the normative goal of medicine of identifying diseases encounters two fundamental questions: (1) Is biology itself normative and can it define the “natural” state? (2) Can medicine rely on knowledge other than biological knowledge to identify what goes wrong? As a normative discipline, medicine comes into conflict with the multiplicity in the very ontology of diseases, which needs to be complemented with epistemic pluralism. Philosophy of medicine therefore needs to explore the sources of that normativity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For naturalist accounts, see Boorse 1977, 1997, 2014, and Chap. 9. For normativist positions, see Nordenfelt 2007 and Chap. 12.

  2. 2.

    Following Searle (1995), Hacking characterizes social constructions as “ontologically subjective but epistemologically objective items” (Hacking 1999, 22).

  3. 3.

    Not all biological individuals are organisms; organisms are characterized by the properties that provide their capacity to persist.

  4. 4.

    Understood as an account that does not provide all the detail, or leaves things out in some respect in relation to the domain of full material realization of a system, but which still provides a literal perspective, without falsity, that is relevant for some purpose. In contrast to abstraction, idealization deviates from the literal perspective and introduces false assumptions, such as infinite population numbers (Godfrey-Smith 2014, 21).

  5. 5.

    The notion of organism has been brought into question in several ways in the past and considered not to be theoretical; but it has acquired a new relevance in more recent biology and philosophy.

  6. 6.

    The theory of autopoiesis considers organization as a criterion to demarcate life from non-life.

  7. 7.

    “[I]t would be absurd for humans even to make such an attempt or to hope that there may yet arise a Newton who could make comprehensible even the generation of a blade of grass according to natural laws that no intention has ordered; rather, we must absolutely deny this insight to human beings.” (Kant 1790, §75).

  8. 8.

    Recent evolutionary biology has addressed the issue of “organismality,” as an account of different kinds of organization produced by evolution. Meanwhile, evo-devo has pursued generative explanations by including developmental processes in evolutionary accounts.

  9. 9.

    “Medical thought has never stopped alternating between these two representations of disease, between these two kinds of optimism, always finding some good reason for one or the other attitude in a newly explained pathogenesis. Deficiency diseases and all infectious or parasitic diseases favour the ontological theory, while endocrine disturbances and all diseases beginning with dys- support the dynamic or functional theory.” (Canguilhem 1991, 40–41).

  10. 10.

    For instance, Wouters (2003) distinguishes four notions of function in biology. One of them views function as the activity a part or organ performs or is capable of performing, without considering the use of this activity. For many authors, this is the most neutral concept of function; but as it does not support multiple realizability, it is a rather unusual concept. The other three notions view function as use or role, because they attempt to identify the role or roles of a given structure or part, understood as its contribution to survival and reproduction (in the case of function as biological advantage), to a selected effect (in the case of the etiological function) or to a complex activity (in the case of function as causal role).

  11. 11.

    The question of the ontology of diseases will not be pursued here.

  12. 12.

    According to Bechtel and Abrahamsen (2005, 423), a mechanism is “a structure performing a function in virtue of its component parts, component operations, and their organization” so that the orchestrated mechanism is responsible for one or more phenomena. This approach is considered to be as useful to understand pathological phenomena as it is physiological ones, insofar as both can be described as mechanisms. In this respect, Nervi follows Craver (2001, 67) who explicitly maintains that his account of functions “does not appeal to any sense of adaptiveness in an environment; instead it appeals only to roles in contextual systems […which] may be adaptive or destructive.”

  13. 13.

    We are told, for example, that “there are many more states of an organ or organ system compatible with disease than with health. […] The same point can be made about function. There are many more states of an organ or organ system compatible with its failing to perform its function than with its performing its function.” (Garson 2013, 326).

  14. 14.

    See footnote 4 above.

References

  • Ahn, A. C., Tewari, M., Poon, C.-S., & Phillips, R. S. (2006a). The limits of reductionism in medicine. Could systems biology offer an alternative? PLoS Medicine, 3(6), e208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ahn, A. C., Tewari, M., Poon, C.-S., & Phillips, R. S. (2006b). The clinical applications of a systems approach. PLoS Medicine, 3(7), e209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R. (2000). Against normal function. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 31(1), 33–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanistic alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44, 542–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1997). A rebuttal on health. In J. M. Humber & R. F. Almeder (Eds.), What is disease? (pp. 1–134). Totowa: Humana Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (2014). A second rebuttal on health. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 39(6), 683–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (2016). Goals of medicine. In É. Giroux (Ed.), Naturalism in the philosophy of health: Issues and implications. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canguilhem, G. (1991). The normal and the pathological. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casado, A., & Etxeberria, A. (2013). Towards autonomy-within-illness: Applying the triadic approach to the principles of bioethics. In H. Carel & R. Cooper (Eds.), Health, illness and disease. Philosophical essays (pp. 57–75). Newcastle: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2001). Role functions, mechanisms, and hierarchy. Philosophy of Science, 68(1), 53–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2013). Functions and mechanisms: A perspectivalist view. In P. Huneman (Ed.), Functions: Selection and mechanisms (pp. 133–158). Dordrecht/New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2010). It is not possible to reduce biological explanations to explanations in chemistry and/or physics. In F. J. Ayala & R. Arp (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology (pp. 32–47). Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell Pub.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2011). Emerging sciences and new conceptions of disease; or, beyond the monogenomic differentiated cell lineage. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 1(1), 119–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Efstathiou, S. (2013). Beauty and health as medical norms: The case of Nazi medicine. In H. Carel & R. Cooper (Eds.), Health, illness and disease (Philosophical essays, pp. 211–228). Newcastle: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel, G. L. (1977). The need for a new medical model: A challenge for biomedicine. Science, 196(4286), 129–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2009). Defining “health” and “disease”. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 40, 221–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fulford, K. W. M. (2001). ‘What is (mental) disease?’: An open letter to Christopher Boorse. Journal of Medical Ethics, 27, 80–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2013). The functional sense of mechanism. Philosophy of Science, 80(3), 317–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S. F., Sapp, J., & Tauber, A. (2012). A symbiotic view of life: We have never been individuals. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 87(4), 325–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giroux, E. (2010). Après canguilhem: définir la santé et la maladie. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2014). Philosophy of biology. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1994). The evolution of life in the Earth. Scientific American, 271(4), 84–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grene, M. (1976). Philosophy of medicine: Prolegomena to a philosophy of science. In PSA proceedings of the biennial meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (Vol. 2, pp. 77–93).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, F. (2011). What systems biology can tell us about disease. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 33(4), 477–496.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrington, A. (1996). Reenchanted science: Holism in German culture from Wilhelm II to Hitler. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P. M., & Williamson, J. (2010). Function and organization: Comparing the mechanisms of protein synthesis and natural selection. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 41, 279–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, F. (1973). The logic of life: A history of heredity. New York: Pantheon books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, F. (1977). Evolution and tinkering. Science, 196, 1161–1166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1790). Critique of the power of judgment (P. Guyer, Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (2010). It is possible to reduce biological explanations to explanations in chemistry and/or physics. In F. J. Ayala & R. Arp (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology (pp. 19–31). Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell Pub.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendler, K. S., Zachar, P., & Craver, C. (2011). What kinds of things are psychiatric disorders? Psychological Medicine, 41, 1143–1150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (2008). Do we need theory to study disease? Lessons from cancer disease and their implications for mental illness. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 51(3), 367–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingma, E. (2013). Health and disease: Social constructivism as a combination of naturalism and normativism. In H. Carel & R. Cooper (Eds.), Health illness and disease: Philosophical essays (pp. 37–56). Newcastle: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Draden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcum, J. A. (2011). Medical cure and progress. The case of type-1 diabetes. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 54(2), 176–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mebius, A. (2014). A weakened mechanism is still a mechanism: On the causal role of absences in mechanistic explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 45, 43–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moghaddam-Taaheri, S. (2011). Understanding pathology in the context of physiological mechanisms: The practicality of a broken-normal view. Biology and Philosophy, 26(4), 603–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mol, A. (1998). Lived reality and the multiplicity of norms: A critical tribute to George Canguilhem. Economy and Society, 27(2–3), 274–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A., Ruiz-Mirazo, K., & Barandiaran, X. E. (2011). The impact of the paradigm of complexity on the foundational frameworks of biology and cognitive science. In C. A. Hooker, D. V. Gabbay, P. Thagard, & J. Woods (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science (pp. 311–333). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moss, L. (2012). Is the philosophy of mechanism philosophy enough? Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 164–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nervi, M. (2010). Mechanisms, malfunctions and explanation in medicine. Biology and Philosophy, 25, 215–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordenfelt, L. (2007). The concepts of health and illness revisited. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 10, 5–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordenfelt, L. (2016). A defense of a holistic notion of health. In É. Giroux (Ed.), Naturalism in the philosophy of health: Issues and implications. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley, M. A. (2010). Making knowledge in synthetic biology: Design meets kludge. Biological Theory, 4(4), 378–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paxson, H. (2008). Post-Pasteurian cultures: The microbiopolitics of raw-milk cheese in the United States. Cultural Anthropology, 23, 15–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valles, S. A. (2012). Evolutionary medicine at twenty: Rethinking adaptationism and disease. Biology and Philosophy, 27(2), 241–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, M., Ruiz-Esteban, R., & Mestre de Juan, M. J. (2010). Chaos, fractals, and our concept of disease. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 53(4), 584–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogt, H., Ulvestad, E., Eriksen, T. E., & Getz, L. (2014). Getting personal: Can systems medicine integrate scientific and humanistic conceptions of the patient? Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 942(20), 942–952.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolkenhauer, O., & Green, S. (2013). The search for organizing principles as a cure against reductionism in systems medicine. The FEBS Journal, 280(23), 5938–5948.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wouters, A. G. (2003). Four notions of biological function. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 34(4), 633–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Funding for this research was provided by the grant IT 590–13 from the Basque government, and by the grant FFI2011-25665 from the Spanish government’s Ministerio de Economía y Competitivad. I thank Elodie Giroux for her kind invitation both to participate in the Lyon workshop and to collaborate in this volume; and also Antonio Casado da Rocha for his comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Arantza Etxeberria .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Etxeberria, A. (2016). Biological Organization and Pathology: Three Views on the Normativity of Medicine. In: Giroux, É. (eds) Naturalism in the Philosophy of Health. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-29091-1_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics