Skip to main content

Values in Caring for Proof

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Mathematical Cultures

Part of the book series: Trends in the History of Science ((TRENDSHISTORYSCIENCE))

Abstract

In response to Gowers (Mathematical knowledge. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 33–58, 2007) who sought qualities of proofs that make them memorable, we suggest converting this into qualities that make proofs reconstructible. But Re-constructibility is a property of the person, situation and proof. This leads us to consider what values are being displayed when students are offered proofs, and the notion that, as a caring profession, there are tensions between showing care for students and care for mathematics. We offer interpretations of the commonly used words appreciation, comprehension and understanding in relation to proofs, and use these to analyse and develop three proofs of the irrationality of √2, in order to suggest that in addition to immersion in the mechanics of proof such as justifications, warrants, sentence structure and the like, what students need in order to be able to re-construct proofs is to internalise the act of personal narrative or self-explanation concerning not simply the steps and stages of a proof, but their appreciation, comprehension and understanding of the key ideas, including conceptual insights and technical handles.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We have added a step in the calculation where Gowers goes directly to the final simplified form.

References

  • Avigad, J. (2008). Understanding proofs. In P. Mancosu (Ed.), The philosophy of mathematical practice (pp. 317–353). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Balacheff, N. (2010). Bridging knowing and proving in mathematics: A didactical perspective. In G. Hanna, H. N. Jahnke & H. Pulte (Eds.), Explanation and proof in mathematics. philosophical and educational perspectives (pp. 115–136). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauersfeld, H. (1988). Interaction, construction, and knowledge—Alternative perspectives for mathematics education. In D. A. Grouws & T. J. Cooney (Eds.), Perspectives on research on effective mathematics teaching: Research agenda for mathematics education (Vol. 1, pp. 27–46). Reston: NCTM and Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, A. (1991). Mathematical enculturation: A cultural perspective on mathematics education. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bogomolny, A. (Webref). Square root of 2 is irrational, from interactive mathematics miscellany and puzzles. http://www.cut-the-knot.org/proofs/sq_root.shtml. Accessed November 06, 2013.

  • Brousseau, G. (1997). Theory of Didactical Situations in Mathematics: didactiques des mathématiques, 1970–1990 (N. Balacheff, M. Cooper, R. Sutherland & V. Warfield, Trans.). Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, S., Collins, A., & Duguid, P. (1989). Situated cognition and the culture of learning. Educational Researcher, 18(1), 32–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byers, W. (2007). How mathematicians think: Using ambiguity, contradiction and paradox to create mathematics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Chi, M., & Bassok, M. (1989). Learning from examples via self-explanation. In L. Resnick (Ed.), Knowing, learning and instruction: Essays in honour of Robert Glaser. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chi, M., Bassok, M., Lewis, M., Reimann, P., & Glaser, R. (1989). Self-explanations: How students study and use examples in learning to solve problems. Cognitive Science, 13, 145–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conway, J. (2006). The power of mathematics. In A. Blackwell & D. MacKay, (Eds.), Power, Darwin College Lectures 16. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, B. (1996). Teaching mathematics: Towards a sound alternative. New York: Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Villiers, M. (1990). The role and function of proof in mathematics. Pythagoras, 24(1), 17–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Villiers, M. (2010). Experimentation and proof in mathematics. In G. Hanna, H. N. Jahnke, & H. Pulte (Eds.), Explanation and proof: Philosophical and educational perspectives (pp. 205–221). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeVito, J. (2006). Teaching as relational development. New Directions for Teaching and Learning., 1986(26), 51–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, T. (1999). Why Johnny can’t prove. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 38, 85–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ernest, P. (1989). The knowledge, beliefs and attitudes of the mathematics teacher: A model. Journal of Education for Teaching: International research and pedagogy., 15(1), 13–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freudenthal, H. (1978). Weeding and sowing: Preface to a science of mathematics education. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gattegno, C. (1987). The science of education part I: Theoretical considerations. New York: Educational Solutions.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilat, D. (2012). Gauss’ Lemma and the irrationality of roots, revised. Mathematics Magazine, 85(2), 114–116.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, L. (2002). Reclaiming caring in teaching and teacher education. New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gowers, W. (2007). Mathematics, memory and mental arithmetic. In M. Leng, A. Paseau, & M. Potter (Eds.), Mathematical knowledge (pp. 33–58). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hackenberg, A. (2005). A model of mathematical learning and caring relations. For the Learning of Mathematics, 25(1), 45–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Handa, Y. (2011). What does understanding mathematics mean for teachers? Relationship as a metaphor for knowing (Studies in Curriculum Theory Series). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, G. (1995). Challenges to the importance of proof. For the Learning of Mathematics, 15(3), 42–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, G. (2000). Proof, explanation and exploration: An overview. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 44, 5–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, G. (2007). The ongoing value of proof. In P. Boero (Ed.), Theorems in schools: From history, epistemology and cognition to classroom practice (pp. 3–18). Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, G., & Barbeau, E. (2009). Proofs as bearers of mathematical knowledge. In G. Hanna, H. N. Jahnke & H. Pulte (Eds.), Explanation and proof in mathematics. Philosophical and educational perspectives (pp. 85–100). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heaton, R. (1992). Who is minding the mathematics content? A case study of a fifth-grade teacher. The Elementary School Journal, 93(2), 153–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hemmi, K. (2006). Approaching proof in a community of mathematical practice (Doctoral dissertation, Stockholm).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hemmi, K. (2008) Students’ encounter with proof: The condition of transparency. ZDM, 40(3), 413–426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodds, M., Alcock, L., & Inglis, M. (2014). Self-explanation training improves proof comprehension. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 45, 98–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holt, J. (1964). How children fail. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jahnke, H. N. (2009). Proof and the empirical sciences. In F.-L. Lin, F.-J. Hsieh, G. Hanna, M. de Villiers (Eds.), Proceedings of the ICMI Study 19 conference: Proof and Proving in Mathematics Education Vols. I & II (vol. I, pp. 238–245). The Department of Mathematics, National Taiwan Normal University, Taipei, Taiwan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2002). Maps of bounded rationality: A perspective on intuitive judgment and choice (Nobel Prize Lecture), in Les Prix Nobel, Frangsmyr, T (Ed.). Accessed November 2013 at http://www.nobel.se/economics/laureates/2002/kahnemann-lecture.pdf

  • Kahneman, D., & Frederick, S. (2002). Representativeness revisited: Attribute substitution in intuitive judgement. In T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, & D. Kahneman (Eds.), Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment (pp. 49–81). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Knipping, C. (2008). A method for revealing structures of argumentation in classroom proving processes. ZDM, 40(3), 427–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, E., & Mason, J. (1992). Teaching mathematics: Action and awareness. Milton Keynes: Open University.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacMillan, E. (2009). Argumentation and proof: Investigating the effect of teaching mathematical proof on students’ argumentation skills. Unpublished DPhil Thesis. Oxford: University of oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (2011). Explanation in mathematics. Stanford Encyclopedia. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mathematics-explanation/

  • Manin, Y. I. (1998). Truth, rigour, and common sense. In H. G. Dales & G. Oliveri (Eds.), Truth in mathematics (pp. 147–159). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mariotti, A. (2006). Proof and proving in mathematics education. In A. Gutiérrez & P. Boero (Eds.), Handbook of research on the psychology of mathematics education: Past, present and future (pp. 173–204). Rotterdam/Taipei: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, J., Burton L., & Stacey K. (1982/2010). Thinking mathematically, London: Addison Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, J. (2002a). Researching your own practice: The discipline of noticing. London: RoutledgeFalmer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, J. (2002b). Mathematics teaching practice: A guide for university and college lecturers. Chichester: Horwood Publishing.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Mason, J. (2008). Being mathematical with & in front of learners: Attention, awareness, and attitude as sources of differences between teacher educators, teachers & learners. In T. Wood (Series Ed.) & B. Jaworski (Vol. Ed.), International handbook of mathematics teacher education: Vol. 4. The Mathematics Teacher Educator as a Developing Professional (pp. 31–56). Rotterdam, The Netherlands: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, J. (2010). Expressions of desire: (Re)flections on (Re)presentation. Mediterranean Journal for Mathematics Education, 9(1), xxx.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, J., Graham, A., Pimm, D., & Gowar, N. (1985). Routes to, roots of algebra. Milton Keynes: The Open University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, J., & Johnston-Wilder, S. (2004). Designing and using mathematical tasks. Milton Keynes: Open University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, J., & Pimm, D. (1984). Generic examples: Seeing the general in the particular. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 15, 227–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mejia-Ramos, J., Fuller, E., Weber, K., Rhoads, K., & Samkoff, A. (2012). An assessment model for proof comprehension in undergraduate mathematics. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 79(1), 3–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mejia-Ramos, J., & Weber, K. (2014). Why and how mathematicians read proofs: Further evidence from a survey study. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 85(2), 161–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michener, E. (1978). Understanding understanding mathematics. Cognitive Science, 2, 361–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, S. J., & Montague, D. (2012). Picturing irrationality. Mathematics Magazine, 85(2), 110–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moyer, P. (2002). Are we having fun yet? How teachers use manipulatives to teach mathematics. Educational Studies in Mathematics Education 175–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noddings, N. (1996). The caring professional. In S. Gordon, P. Benner, & N. Noddings (Eds.), Caregiving: Readings in knowledge, practice, ethics, and politics (pp. 160–172). Philedelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noddings, N. (2003). Is teaching a practice? Journal of Philosophy of Education, 37(2), 241–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, T. (2006, January). What is fifth grade? Phi Beta Kappan 373–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, W. (1968). Forms of intellectual and ethical development in the college years: A scheme. New York: Holt, Rhinehart & Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potter, M. (1976). Short-term conceptual memory for pictures. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 2(5), 509–522.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raman, M. (2003). Key ideas: What are they and how can they help us understand how people view proof? Educational Studies in Mathematics, 52(3), 319–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raman, M., Sandefur, J., Birky, G., Campbell, C., & Somers, K. (2009). Is that a proof? Using video to teach and learn how to prove at the university level. In F.-L. Lin, F.-J. Hsieh, G. Hanna & M. de Villiers (Eds.), Proceedings of ICMI study 19 on proof and proving in mathematics education. (Vol. 2, pp. 154–159).Taipei: National Taiwan Normal University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rav, Y. (2007). A critique of a formalist-mechanist version of the justification of arguments in mathematicians’ proof practices. Philosophia Mathematica, 15(3), 291–320.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Reid, D., & Knipping, C. (2010). Proof in mathematics education: Research, learning and teaching. Rotterdam: Sense.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandefur, J., Mason, J., Stylianides, G., & Watson, A. (2013). Generating and using examples in the proving process. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 83(3), 323–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scataglini-Belghitar, G., & Mason, J. (2012). Establishing appropriate conditions: Students learning to apply a theorem. IJSME, 10(4), 927–953.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selden, A. (2012). Transitions and proof and proving at tertiary level. In G. Hanna & M. de Villiers (Eds.), Proof and proving in mathematics education (pp. 391–420). Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. (1954). The science of learning and the art of teaching. Harvard Educational Review, 24(2), 86–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, M., Grover, B., & Henningsen, M. (1996). Building student capacity for mathematical thinking and reasoning: An analysis of mathematical tasks used in reform classrooms. American Educational Research Journal, 33(2), 455–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thurston, W. (1994). Proof and Progress in Mathematics. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 30(7) April, 161–177; (reprinted in For The Learning of Mathematics, 15(1) 1995, 29–37).

    Google Scholar 

  • Thurston, W. P. (1995). On proof and progress in mathematics. For the learning of mathematics, 15(1), 29–37. (Previously published in the Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 1994).

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1958). The uses of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trigwell, K., & Prosser, M. (1996). Changing approaches to teaching: A relational perspective. Studies in Higher Education, 21(3), 275–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, A. (2002). Teaching for understanding. In L. Haggarty (Ed.) Aspects of teaching and learning mathematics in the secondary school: Perspectives on practice (pp. 153–163). London: Routledge/Falmer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, K., & Alcock, L. (2005). Using warranted implications to understand and validate proofs. For the Learning of Mathematics, 25(1), 34–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winbourne, P., & Watson, A. (1998) Participating in learning mathematics through shared local practices in classrooms. In A. Watson (Ed.), Situated cognition and the learning of mathematics. (Chapter 7, pp. 93–104). Oxford: University of Oxford Department of Educational Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, D., Bruner, J., & Ross, G. (1976). The role of tutoring in problem solving. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 17, 89–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yackel, E., & Cobb, P. (1996a). Constructivist, emergent, and sociocultural perspectives in the context of developmental research. Educational Psychologist, 31(3–4), 171–190. doi:10.1080/00461520.1996.9653265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yackel, E., & Cobb, P. (1996b). Sociomathematical norms, argumentation, and autonomy in mathematics. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 27(4), 458–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Mason .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix: Extending the Carpet Reasoning

Appendix: Extending the Carpet Reasoning

The carpet-proof extends to √3 using either a triangle or a square, but what details need to be checked, what narrative has to be supplied to turn either of the diagrams into a proof, and how does it depend on to whom the reasoning is to be presented?

For the triangle version, the uncovered triangle turns out to be integer sided and equal in area to the total area of the three overlap triangles. For the square version, the three lightly shaded squares are each one third of the area of the whole. Let them have edge length b while the overall has edge length a; the uncovered area is made up of six squares each with edge length (a − b)/2 and their total area is equal to the area of the two mid-shaded squares with edge length a − 3w, which overlap in the little dark-shaded square with edge length b − 2w. Although the mid-shaded squares are each equal in area to three of the small white squares, these do not have integral sides unless a and b are of the same parity. By constructing a square which has twice the edge length of one of these, with edge length 2(a − 3w) < a, it can be presented as 3 squares each with edge length a − b < b and so the infinite descent works.

The conceptual insight to construct a double sized square comes from Miller and Montague (2012, p. 110). Instead of requiring that some visible region be decomposed appropriately, they extended or varied the construction to construct a new object which can be suitably decomposed and yet involves integer sides smaller than the initial ones. Miller and Montague also wondered about other surds. They found the triangle version for √3, which they extended to √6 and √10 with greatly increased effort in calculating length, taking into account the multiple overlaps.

But for √15 and larger, the newly constructed triangle turns out not to be smaller than the original and so the reasoning breaks down (Miller and Montague 2012, p. 112). They observe that the method could not in case extend indefinitely, as some triangular numbers are also square!

Aiming for √5 using the corners idea with pentagons turns out to be rather more difficult, because the overlaps are not pentagons and the uncovered floor area is more than a pentagon.

Miller and Montague (2012, p. 112–113) found a clever way of decomposing the overlaps into two pieces, a regular pentagon at the top and a triangle at the bottom. The triangle matches the adjacent uncovered region (as indicated in the right-hand figure by the completion of the bottom overlap pentagon). It takes some facility to relate the edge-lengths of the resulting regular pentagons and the edge length of the central regular pentagon in order to verify that the they all have integer sides and so constitute an infinite descent and so a contradiction. Let a 2 = 5b 2, with the large pentagon having edge-length a and the smaller ones edge-length b. Then the inner uncovered pentagon has edge-length 5b − 2a, and the short edges of the kite are length a − 2b. Since

$$\frac{5b - 2a}{a - 2b} = \frac{a}{b} \; \text{if} \; \text{and}\; \text{only}\;\text{if} \;a^{2} = 5b^{2}$$

 and since 0 < 5b − 2a < a and 0 < a − 2b < b, the contradiction arises. There seem to be some resonances with the algebraic proof!

However, extending this approach to other numbers is likely to be increasingly difficult, since for d ≥ 6 it is even less clear how to reconfigure the overlaps, and for d > 25 placing regular d-gons in the corners of a regular d-gon leads to extra overlaps (but see Bogomolny webref for alternative geometrical proofs). It is even less clear how cube-roots or others might be handled geometrically.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this paper

Cite this paper

Mason, J., Hanna, G. (2016). Values in Caring for Proof. In: Larvor, B. (eds) Mathematical Cultures. Trends in the History of Science. Birkhäuser, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-28582-5_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics