Skip to main content

Exploratory Uses of Scientific Models

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
How to Do Science with Models

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in Philosophy ((BRIEFSPHILOSOPH))

Abstract

This chapter discusses a variety of closely related uses of models which are best described collectively as ‘exploratory modeling’. The importance of exploration to science has recently been emphasized by a number of historians and philosophers of science writing on scientific experimentation, and the chapter begins by reviewing this lively debate. Following a clarification of the meaning of ‘exploration’ by distinguishing between a ‘convergent’ and a ‘divergent’ sense, the concept is then applied to the case of scientific models. In particular, four different functions of exploratory models are distinguished: they may function as a starting point for future inquiry, feature in proof-of-principle demonstrations, generate potential explanations of observed (types of) phenomena, and may lead to reassessments of the suitability of the target. These functions are neither mutually exclusive, nor are they thought to exhaust the spectrum of possible exploratory uses to which models may be put. Examples for each of the four types of exploratory uses are provided and range from models in sociodynamics (traffic flow models) to proposed mechanisms of molecular rearrangements in physical organic chemistry. The chapter closes with a discussion of the prospects and limitations of exploratory modeling and concludes that exploration deserves a place alongside explanation and prediction as one of the core functions of scientific modeling.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 59.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For recent collections of papers on the problem of scientific understanding, see [57, 60].

  2. 2.

    It is worth keeping in mind that the term ‘model’, as discussed in Chap. 1 (Sect. 1.2), used to have a more restrictive meaning, referring primarily to mechanical models, with other models commonly referred to as ‘analogies’.

  3. 3.

    For a discussion of mature symbol systems as a form of ‘“cognitive scaffolding”, which allow their users to “offload” or “externalize” cognitive load’, see [33, p. 59].

  4. 4.

    This is one of the reasons why experimentation and exploration are not mutually exclusive; drawing a contrast between ‘the experimental’ and ‘the explorative’ gives rise to a number of false dichotomies, of the sort found in [59, p. 191].

  5. 5.

    Quoted after [48, p. 351]. The French original is: ‘…elle est dans l'hypothèse de Coulomb sur la nature de l'action magnétique; on croyait à cette hypothèse comme à un fait; elle écartait absolument toute idée d'action entre l'électricité et les prétendus fils magnétiques’ [49].

  6. 6.

    Both experiments were exploratory, insofar as no firm theoretical foundation was available at the time; therefore, an alternative interpretation might consider the first experiment—which aimed at demonstrating the existence of a causal link—an instance of ‘convergent’ exploration, whereas the second experiment, with its simultaneous variation of different parameters, might be considered as a case of ‘divergent’ exploration.

  7. 7.

    Whereas early minimal models tend to derive their dynamics from system-level equations, modern synthetic models in contemporary theoretical ecology tend to be ‘bottom-up, representing many small spatial units or individuals and their behavior’, with their ‘system dynamics emerg[ing] from the interaction of the components’ [36, p. 367].

  8. 8.

    Hausman’s account of modeling as a form of conceptual exploration, however, is weaker than what I have in mind: as Uskali Mäki observes, on Hausman’s account, ‘a model as such contains no truth claims about the world, it is rather a definition of a predicate given by the assumptions of the model’ [56, p. 15]; only theoretical hypotheses about the applicability of model to particular situation are truth-valued. I agree with Mäki that this insulates models too much from potential challenges arising from the realist concern with truth.

  9. 9.

    Michael Redhead seems to entertain a similar idea when he suggests that, ‘[b]y exploring models […] for a theory T we can probe how approximations A M to the model M […] misrepresent M and the true behaviour of M as opposed to A M can now be used as a guide how to T behaves’ [54, p. 153].

  10. 10.

    On this point, see [58, p. 119]. While Bailer-Jones is one of the few philosophers of science to explicitly state that models provide ‘material for exploration’ (ibid.), she appears to regard exploration as mainly associated with an understanding of models as metaphors; this, it seems to me, does not do justice to the specific character of model-based exploration discussed in the present chapter.

  11. 11.

    For a detailed account of the evolution and timeline of traffic flow models, see [50].

  12. 12.

    The Lotka-Volterra equations do, in fact, permit for an equilibrium solution; however, the equilibrium point is unstable, so that any perturbation—however small—suffices to trigger the oscillatory behaviour.

  13. 13.

    My discussion of this example draws heavily on [40].

  14. 14.

    Quoted after [44, p. 222].

  15. 15.

    For a discussion of Ingold’s system of classifications, see [45].

  16. 16.

    Quoted after [40, p. 567].

  17. 17.

    Quoted after [40, p. 571].

  18. 18.

    The notion of a ‘how-possibly’ question goes back to the philosopher of history William Herbert Dray who had argued that ‘the demand for explanation is, in some contexts, satisfactorily met if what happened is merely shown to have been possible; there is no need to go on to show that it was necessary as well’ [46, p. 157] That is, how-possibly explanations are offered as genuine and complete explanations of particular phenomena without pretending to subsume them under general laws or generalizations (see [55] for a more recent discussion).

  19. 19.

    Something like this seems to be Jordi Cat’s point in [51], though he appears to think that scientists and philosophers alike have tended to overlook the importance of initial and boundary conditions.

  20. 20.

    The difficulty of stabilizing phenomena in the absence of agreed-upon criteria for what counts as a successful experiment is known as the ‘experimenter’s regress’; for a discussion of its analogue in the case of scientific models and simulations (‘simulationist’s regress’), see [52].

  21. 21.

    Quoted after [47, p. 140].

  22. 22.

    The same holds for other many-body models such as the Hubbard model, discussed in Chap. 3 (Sect. 3.3). As I have noted elsewhere, often ‘the “exploratory” phase of understanding a proposed many-body model and cultivating intuitions about the interplay of themicroscopic mechanisms it is designed to represent is drawn out over many years; whether the model will in the end match an empirical phenomenon in many cases remains an open question’ [53, p. 263].

References

  1. C.G. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science (Free Press, New York, 1965)

    Google Scholar 

  2. M. Scriven, Explanations, predictions, and laws, in Scientific Explanation, Space, and Time, ed. by H. Feigl, G. Maxwell (University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1962), pp. 170–230

    Google Scholar 

  3. W. Salmon, Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1984)

    Google Scholar 

  4. M. Strevens, No understanding without explanation. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 44(3), 510–515 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. A. Gopnik, Explanation as orgasm and the drive for causal knowledge: the function, evolution, and phenomenology of the theory formation system, in Cognition and Explanation, ed. by F.C. Keil, R.A. Wilson (MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 2000), pp. 299–323

    Google Scholar 

  6. A. Alexandra, R. Northcott, It’s just a feeling: why economic models do not explain. J. Econ. Method. 20(3), 262–267 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. P. Godfrey-Smith, The strategy of model-based science. Biol. Philos. 21(5), 725–740 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. W. Thomson, Notes on Lectures on Molecular Dynamics and the Wave Theory of Light (Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, 1884)

    Google Scholar 

  9. S.W. Yi, The nature of model-based understanding in condensed matter physics. Mind Soc. 3(1), 81–91 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. H.W. de Regt, Understanding and scientific explanation, in Scientific Understanding: Philosophical Perspectives, ed. by H.W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, K. Eigner (University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, 2009), pp. 21–42

    Google Scholar 

  11. T. Kisiel, Scientific discovery: logical, psychological, or hermeneutical?, in Explorations in Phenomenology: Papers of the Society for Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy, ed. by D. Carr, E.S. Casey (Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1973), pp. 263–284

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  12. M. Stöckler, On modeling and simulations as instruments for the study of complex systems, in Science at Century’s End: Philosophical Questions on the Progress and Limits of Science, ed. by M. Carrier, G.J. Massey, L. Ruetsche (University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, 1997), pp. 355–373

    Google Scholar 

  13. M.S. Morgan, The World in the Model: How Economists Work and Think (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2012)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. D.E. Berlyne, Conflict, Arousal and Curiosity (McGraw-Hill, New York, 1960)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. J.A. Simpson, E.S. Weiner (eds.), The Oxford English Dictionary, vol. V (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1989)

    Google Scholar 

  16. J.C. Maxwell, in The Scientific Papers of James Clerk Maxwell, vol. 1, ed. by W.D. Niven. (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1890)

    Google Scholar 

  17. F. Steinle, Entering new fields: exploratory uses of experimentation. Philos. Sci. 64, S65–S74 (1997). (Proceedings of the PSA1996, Pt. II)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. R.M. Burian, Exploratory experimentation and the role of histochemical techniques in the work of Jean Brachet, 1938–1952. Hist. Philos. Life Sci. 19(1), 27–45 (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  19. U. Feest, Exploratory experiments, concept formation, and theory construction in psychology, in Scientific Concepts and Investigative Practice, ed. by U. Feest, F. Steinle (de Gruyter, Berlin, 2012), pp. 167–189

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  20. C.K. Waters, The nature and context of exploratory experimentation: an introduction to three case studies of exploratory research. Hist. Philos. Life Sci. 29(3), 275–284 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  21. K.C. Elliott, Varieties of exploratory experimentation in nanotoxicology. Hist. Philos. Life Sci. 29(3), 313–336 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  22. D. Gooding, Experiment and the Making of Meaning: Human Agency in Scientific Observation and Experiment (Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1990)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  23. J.H. Holland, Emergence. Philosophica 59(1), 11–40 (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  24. J. Roughgarden, A. Bergman, S. Shafir, C. Taylor, Adaptive computation in ecology and evolution: a guide for future research, in Adaptive Individuals in Evolving Populations: Models and Algorithms, ed. by R.K. Belew, M. Mitchell (Addison-Wesley, Boston, 1996), pp. 25–30

    Google Scholar 

  25. N. Goldenfeld, Lectures on Phase Transitions and the Renormalization Group (Addison-Wesley, Boston, 1992)

    Google Scholar 

  26. R. Batterman, Asymptotics and the role of minimal models. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 53(1), 21–38 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. D. Hausman, Economic methodology in a nutshell. J. Econ. Perspect. 3(2), 115–127 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. W.C. Wimsatt, Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to Reality (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., 2007)

    Google Scholar 

  29. P. Taylor, Revising models and generating theory. Oikos 54(1), 121–126 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. A. Gelfert, Mathematical formalisms in scientific practice: from denotation to model-based representation. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 42(2), 272–286 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. M. Boumans, Built-in justification, in Models as mediators: perspectives on natural and social science, ed. by M.S. Morgan, M. Morrison (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999), pp. 66–96

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  32. M. Hesse, Models in physics. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 4(15), 198–214 (1953)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. A. Gelfert, Symbol systems as collective representational resources: Mary Hesse, Nelson Goodman, and the problem of scientific representation. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 4(6), 52–61 (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  34. P.G. Gipps, A behavioural car-following model for computer simulation. Transport. Res. Part B: Method. 15(2), 105–111 (1981)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. M. Morrison, M.S. Morgan, Models as mediating instruments, in Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science, ed. by M.S. Morgan, M. Morrison (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999), pp. 10–37

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  36. V. Grimm, S.F. Railsback, Individual-Based Modeling and Ecology (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2005)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  37. N. Cartwright, How the Laws of Physics Lie (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1983)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  38. J.C. Maxwell, A Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism, vol. 2 (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1873)

    Google Scholar 

  39. C. Ingold, Structure and Mechanism in Organic Chemistry (Cornell University Press, Ithaca, 1953)

    Google Scholar 

  40. G. Fisher, The autonomy of models and explanation: anomalous molecular rearrangements in early twentieth-century physical organic chemistry. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 37(4), 562–584 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. S.G. Sterrett, Morals of model-making. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 46, 31–45 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. A. Levy, Modeling without models. Philos. Stud. 172(3), 781–798 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. J. Kuorikoski, P. Ylikoski, in external representations and scientific understanding. Synthese, 1–21 (forthcoming)

    Google Scholar 

  44. M.J. Nye, From Chemical Philosophy to Theoretical Chemistry: Dynamics of Matter and Dynamics of Disciplines, 1800–1950 (University of California Press, Berkeley, 1993)

    Google Scholar 

  45. J.F. Bunnet, Physical organic terminology, after Ingold. Bull. Hist. Chem. 19, 33–42 (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  46. W.H. Dray, Laws and Explanation in History (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1966)

    Google Scholar 

  47. R. Hughes, The Ising model, computer simulation, and universal physics, in Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science, ed. by M.S. Morgan, M. Morrison (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999), pp. 97–145

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  48. D.C. Christensen, Hans Christian Ørsted: Reading Nature’s Mind (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  49. A.-M. Ampère, in Correspondance d’Ampère, Lettre L596, CNRS, [Online]. Available: http://www.ampere.cnrs.fr/amp-corr596.html. Accessed 22 July 2015

  50. F. van Wageningen-Kessels, H. van Lint, K. Vuik, S. Hoogendoorn, in Genealogy of traffic flow models. EURO J. Transport. Logistics, 1–29 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  51. J. Cat, Modeling cracks and cracking models: structures, mechanisms, boundary conditions, constraints, inconsistencies and the proper domains of natural laws. Synthese 146(3), 447–487 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. A. Gelfert, Scientific models, simulation, and the experimenter’s regress, in Models, Simulations, and Representations, ed. by P. Humphreys, C. Imbert (Routledge, London, 2012), pp. 145–167

    Google Scholar 

  53. A. Gelfert, Strategies of model-building in condensed matter physics: trade-offs as a demarcation criterion between physics and biology? Synthese 190(2), 253–272 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. M. Redhead, Models in physics. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 31(2), 145–163 (1980)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. P. Forber, Confirmation and explaining how possible. Stud. Hist. Philos. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 41(1), 32–40 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. U. Mäki, Remarks on models and their truth. Storia del Pensiero Economico 3(1), 7–19 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  57. H.W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, K. Eigner (eds.), Scientific Understanding: Philosophical Perspectives (University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, 2009)

    Google Scholar 

  58. D. Bailer-Jones, Models, metaphors and analogies, in The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science, ed. by P. Machamer, M. Silberstein (Blackwell, Oxford, 2002), pp. 108–127

    Google Scholar 

  59. S. Ahrens, Experiment and Exploration: Forms of World-Disclosure (Springer, Heidelberg, 2014)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  60. H.W. de Regt (ed.) Understanding without explanation (Special Section). Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 44(3), 505–538 (2013)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Axel Gelfert .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gelfert, A. (2016). Exploratory Uses of Scientific Models. In: How to Do Science with Models. SpringerBriefs in Philosophy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-27954-1_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics