Advertisement

Aping Logic? Albert the Great on Animal Mind and Action

  • Jörg Alejandro TellkampEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind book series (SHPM, volume 16)

Abstract

Albert the Great’s cognitive psychology extends beyond the specific interest of analysing human cognition. This article argues that some animal species, especially primates, have the ability to grasp the material world in a meaningful, i.e., intentional way and display complex types of behaviour that makes it plausible to assume that they have inferential capacities. The physiological similarities between many animal species and human beings allow to establish that those similarities also hold on the cognitive level of sensory knowledge. Thus, if human beings are able to perform certain inferential tasks based solely on sensory information, so can those animals on account of their physiological similarities, namely because they have sense organs and a structured brain that houses the inner senses which are needed to perform those activities. This leads to the idea that, if some animal species engaged in mental activities similar to human mental activities, then they could be said to perform complex tasks, such as basic forms of thinking. But since animals do not have a conceptual apparatus at their disposal, their acts of thinking, or rather proto-thinking, would have to be non-conceptual. Hence, for Albert the Great intelligence in nature manifests itself in various degrees and it does not entail a Cartesian dualistic hiatus between mind and matter.

Keywords

Animal Species Mentalmental Content Animal Life Intentional Content Minor Premise 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Bibliography

Primary Sources

  1. Albertus Magnus. (1890a). In A. Borgnet (Ed.), Opera Omnia I. Priorum analyticorum. Paris: Vives.Google Scholar
  2. Albertus Magnus. (1890b). In A. Borgnet (Ed.), Opera omnia II. Posteriorum analyticorum. Paris: Vives.Google Scholar
  3. Albertus Magnus. (1920). In H. Stadler (Ed.), De animalibus (Vol. 2). Münster: Aschendorff.Google Scholar
  4. Albertus Magnus. (1955). Quaestiones super de animalibus. In B. Filthaut (Ed.), Opera omnia XII (pp. 77–321). Münster: Aschendorff.Google Scholar
  5. Albertus Magnus. (1968). In C. Stroick (Ed.), Opera omnia VII.2. De anima. Münster: Aschendorff.Google Scholar
  6. Albertus Magnus. (1987). In W. Kübel (Ed.), Opera omnia XIV.2. Super Ethica. Münster: Aschendorff.Google Scholar
  7. Albertus Magnus. (2004). In M. Santos Noya (Ed.), Opera omnia I.1a. Super Porphyrium De V universalibus. Münster: Aschendorff.Google Scholar
  8. Albertus Magnus. (2008). In H. Anzulewicz & J. Soeder (Eds.), Opera omnia XXVII.2. De homine. Münster: Aschendorff.Google Scholar
  9. Long, A., & Sedley, D. (Eds.). (1987). The Hellenistic philosophers (Vol. 1). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

  1. Anzulewicz, H. (2002). Konzeptionen und Perspektiven der Sinneswahrnehmung im System Alberts des Grossen. Micrologus, 10, 199–238.Google Scholar
  2. Anzulewicz, H. (2009). Albertus Magnus und die Tiere. In S. Obermaier (Ed.), Tiere und Fabelwesen im Mittelalter (pp. 29–54). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  3. Anzulewicz, H. (2013). Anthropology: The concept of man in Albert the Great. In I. Resnick (Ed.), A companion to Albert the Great. Theology, philosophy, and the sciences (pp. 325–346). Leiden/Boston: Brill.Google Scholar
  4. Bermúdez, J. L. (2003). Thinking without words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Glock, H.-J. (2009). Can animals act for reasons? Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 52, 232–254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Köhler, T. (2008). Homo animal nobilissimum. Konturen des spezifisch Menschlichen in der naturphilosophischen Aristoteleskommentierung des dreizehnten Jahrhunderts (Vol. 1). Leiden/Boston: Brill.Google Scholar
  7. McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Michon, C. (2001). Intentionality and proto-thoughts. In D. Perler (Ed.), Ancient and medieval theories of intentionality (pp. 325–345). Leiden/Boston: Brill.Google Scholar
  9. Morgan, L. (1903). An introduction to comparative psychology (2nd ed.). London/Newcastle: Walter Scott Publishing Co Ltd.Google Scholar
  10. Rescorla, M. (2009). Chrysippus’ dog as a case study in non-linguistic cognition. In R. Lurz (Ed.), The philosophy of animal minds (pp. 52–70). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Roling, B. (2011). Syllogismus brutorum: Die Diskussion der animalischen Rationalität bei Albertus Magnus und ihre Rezeption im Mittelalter und in der frühen Neuzeit. Recherches de Théologie et Philosophie médiévales, 78, 221–275.Google Scholar
  12. Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
  13. Sorabji, R. (1993). Animal minds and human morals. The origins of the western debate. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
  14. Tellkamp, J. (2012). Albert the Great on structure and function of the inner senses. In R. Taylor & I. Omar (Eds.), The Judeo-Christian-Islamic heritage. Philosophical and theological perspectives (pp. 305–324). Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Tellkamp, J. (2013). Albert the Great on perception and non-conceptual content. In L. X. López-Farjeat & J. Tellkamp (Eds.), Philosophical psychology in Arabic thought and the Latin Aristotelianism of the 13th century (pp. 205–221). Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
  16. Thom, P. (2007). Logic and ontology in the syllogistic of Robert Kilwardby. Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Tkacz, M. (2013). Albert the Great on logic, knowledge, and science. In I. Resnick (Ed.), A companion to Albert the Great. Theology, philosophy, and the sciences (pp. 507–540). Leiden/Boston: Brill.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Universidad Autónoma MetropolitanaMexico CityMexico

Personalised recommendations