Advertisement

Augustine on Second-Order Desires and Persons

  • Tomas EkenbergEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind book series (SHPM, volume 16)

Abstract

While commentators have noted interesting parallels between Frankfurt’s and Augustine’s accounts of the freedom of the will, there has been, in this context, little discussion about their respective accounts of personhood. According to Frankfurt, a person is a being capable of forming a certain kind of second-order desires, namely, second-order volitions. In this paper I use Frankfurt’s account of desire and the will to elucidate Augustine’s concept of person. I argue that for Augustine, freedom of the will construed as control over desires or over the causes of action is not a necessary condition for being a person. Rather, he agrees with Frankfurt, who argues that personhood should instead be spelled out in terms of a certain kind of reflexivity or a conative hierarchy.

Keywords

Robust Account Causal Efficacy Robust Conception Hierarchical Account Unwilling Addict 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Bibliography

Primary Sources

  1. Augustine. (1970). De libero arbitrio. In W. M. Green (Ed.), Corpus Christianorum: Series Latina 29. Turnhout: Brepols.Google Scholar
  2. Augustine. (1992). In J. J. O’Donnell (Ed.), Confessions (Vol. 3). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  3. Augustine. (1993). Confessions (trans: Sheed, F. J.). Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  4. Augustine. (2012). The Trinity (De trinitate) (trans: Edmund Hill, O. P.). Hyde Park: New City Press.Google Scholar
  5. Hobbes, T. (1651). Leviathan, or, the matter, forme, and power of a common wealth, ecclesiasticall and civil. London: Andrew Crooke.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

  1. Anscombe, E. A. (1978). Will and emotion. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 7(8), 139–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Brown, P. (2000). Augustine of hippo: A biography. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  3. Burnell, P. (2005). The Augustinian person. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
  4. Cook, C. C. H. (2006). Alcohol, addiction, and Christian ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Davenport, J. J. (2002). Liberty of the higher-order will: Frankfurt and Augustine. Faith and Philosophy, 19(4), 437–461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Ekenberg, T. (2014). Practical rationality and the wills of confessions 8. In W. E. Mann (Ed.), Augustine’s confessions: Philosophy in autobiography (pp. 28–35). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Frankfurt, H. (1987). Identification and wholeheartedness. In F. D. Shoeman (Ed.), Responsibility, character and the emotions (pp. 27–45). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Frede, M. (2011). A free will: Origins of the notion in ancient thought. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  10. Harrison, S. (2006). Augustine’s way into the will: The theological and philosophical significance of De Libero Arbitrio. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Hopkins, J. (1994). Freedom of the will: Parallels between Frankfurt and Augustine. In J. Hopkins (Ed.), Philosophical criticism: Essays and reviews (pp. 3–39). Minneapolis: Banning Press.Google Scholar
  12. Jech, A. (2013). To will one thing. American Philosophical Quarterly, 50(2), 154–165.Google Scholar
  13. Rogers, K. A. (2004). Augustine’s compatibilism. Religious Studies, 40(4), 415–435.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Saarinen, R. (1994). Weakness of the will in medieval thought: From Augustine to Buridan. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  15. Stump, E. (1988). Sanctification, hardening of the heart, and Frankfurt’s concept of free will. Journal of Philosophy, 85, 395–420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Stump, E. (2001). Augustine on free will. In N. Kretzmann & E. Stump (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Augustine (pp. 124–147). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Wetzel, J. (2002). Will and interiority in Augustine: Travels in an unlikely place. Augustinian Studies, 33, 139–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Wetzel, J. (2008). Body double: Saint Augustine and the sexualized will. In T. Hoffman (Ed.), Weakness of will from Plato to the present (pp. 43–58). Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUppsala UniversityUppsalaSweden

Personalised recommendations