Skip to main content

Relevant Alternatives in Epistemology and Logic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 38))

Abstract

The goal of the current paper is to provide an introduction to and survey of the diverse landscape of relevant alternatives theories of knowledge. Emphasis is placed throughout both on the abstractness of the relevant alternatives approach and its amenability to formalization through logical techniques. We present some of the important motivations for adopting the relevant alternatives approach; briefly explore the connections and contrasts between the relevant alternatives approach and related developments in logic, epistemology and philosophy of science; provide a schema for classifying and studying relevant alternatives theories at different levels of abstraction; and present a sample of relevant alternatives theories (contrasting what we call question-first and topic-first theories) that tie our discussion to ongoing debates in the philosophical literature, as well as showcasing techniques for formalizing some of the important positions in these debates.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For this paper, we set aside the tricky question as to in what sense circumstances that are necessarily the case or not the case (such as Goldbach’s conjecture) can be thought to have alternatives – at least for the purposes of inquiry.

  2. 2.

    Note that in Sect. 7.2.9 we discuss a tradition in the epistemology literature that focuses on a notion of “epistemic relevance” that arises from initial concerns quite distinct from those of the RA theorist. The overlapping terminology is no doubt a potential source for confusion, though hopefully not in the current paper.

  3. 3.

    Throughout this section, the critical reader may well want to emphasize the use of the word appearance here in the absence of a proper empirical investigation of these purported linguistic facts.

  4. 4.

    Our ordinary infallibilist tendencies have in fact been used as a weapon in internal debates among RA theorists, suggesting the possibility that some versions of RA theory are better suited to account for these tendencies than others. For instance, DeRose (1995) influentially criticizes Dretske’s version of RA theory as incorrectly predicting that so-called abominable conjunctions – notably “S knows that she has hands and S does not know that she is a handless brain-in-vat” – are felicitous in ordinary conversational contexts.

  5. 5.

    Of course, this may be taken as further linguistic data, in the spirit of that from Sect. 7.2.1.

  6. 6.

    Note that the barn case can be seen to teach a similar lesson to consideration of cartesian skepticism: that one can know something even though one has not ruled out all alternatives. However, the barn case potentially teaches us something more: that what counts as a relevant alternative can vary with the circumstances: the possibility of fake barns may be properly ignored, by knowledge ascribers, under one set of circumstances, but is not properly ignored in another.

  7. 7.

    For a more careful defence of the ‘alternatives’ approach to capturing the relevant parameter that shifts across contexts, see Schaffer (2005b).

  8. 8.

    The reader will note that we make no mention of a notion of ‘context’ anywhere in this semantics. We gloss over the role of context, as follows: context may be thought of as settling the valuation V and, potentially, the set of relevant alternatives R w . Thus, context may be thought of as settling the model in question. We do not explore this thought in any detail here.

  9. 9.

    It also goes some way towards capturing Lewis’ notion of ruling out (Lewis 1996): for him, A is ruled out just in case it holds at no possible world in which the agent has the same memories and sensory experience.

  10. 10.

    We may want to place Dretske and Nozick in this camp too.

  11. 11.

    For recall that we self-consciously model the knowledge of an ideal agent that is always able to “put two and two together” and can therefore maximally extend her knowledge by way of reasoning. To deny of such an agent that closure under known implication is valid is to deny that we ordinary agents are always in principle able to extend our knowledge using self-conscious deductive reasoning by way of known implications.

  12. 12.

    Though perusal of, for instance, Schaffer (2005a,b) quickly reveals the close ties between Schaffer’s views and the RA approach.

  13. 13.

    We mention in footnotes some divergences from important details of Yablo’s theory as we proceed.

  14. 14.

    Yablo in fact embraces a more general conception of a topic: for him, a topic can be associated with a reflexive, symmetric relation on the space of worlds, as opposed to an equivalence relation.

  15. 15.

    Here we see another divergence from Yablo. For Yablo, the subject matter associated with \(\varphi\) is the set of ways that \(\varphi\) could be true and the ways it could be false. More precisely: it is the set of (what Yablo calls) the minimal partial models that succeed in either making \(\varphi\) true or \(\varphi\) false. The reader interested in a proper explication of these notions is directed to Yablo (2014).

  16. 16.

    We depart from Yablo here as follows: for Yablo, elimination of alternatives is inspired by the “tracking” account of Nozick: A is eliminated just in case the agent believes \(\neg A\) and were A to be the case, the agent would not believe \(\neg A\). Despite this change in perspective, the technical details for Yablo’s account and our own are similar in many respects.

References

  • Anderson, A.R., Belnap, N.D.: Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, vol. I. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1975)

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L.: Other minds. Aristot. Soc. Suppl. 20, 122–197 (1946)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., Perry, J.: Situations and Attitudes. MIT, Cambridge (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N.D., Steel, T.B.: The Logic of Questions and Answers. Yale University Press, New Haven (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgess, J.P.: Philosophical Logic. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2009)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R.: Logical Foundations of Probability. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1950)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chellas, B.F.: Modal Logic: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge/New York (1980)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ciardelli, I., Groenendijk, J., Roelofsen, F.: On the semantics and logic of declaratives and interrogatives. Synthese 192, 1689–1728 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S.: How to be a fallibilist. Philos. Perspect. 2, 91–123 (1988)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S.: Contextualism, skepticism and reasons. Noûs 33, 57–89 (1999). Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives, 13, Epistemology

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K.: Solving the skeptical problem. Philos. Rev. 104(1), 1–52 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F.I.: Epistemic operators. J. Philos. 67(24), 1007–1023 (1970)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F.I.: Conclusive reasons. Aust. J. Philos. 49(1), 1–22 (1971)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F.I.: The pragmatic dimension of knowledge. Philos. Stud. 40(3), 363–378 (1981)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J.: Bayes or Bust?: A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory. MIT, Cambridge (1992)

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R.L.: The Semantic Foundations of Logic. Oxford University Press, New York (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L.: Understanding epistemic relevance. Erkenntnis 69, 69–92 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.: Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. J. Philos. 73, 771–791 (1976)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C.L.: Questions. Aust. J. Philos. 36(3), 159–168 (1958)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C.L.: Questions in montague english. Found. Lang. 10(1), 41–53 (1973)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawke, P.: Questions, topics and restricted closure, Philos. Stud. (forthcoming)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawke, P.: The problem of epistemic relevance. Ph.D dissertation, Stanford University (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M.: Relevant alternatives. Philos. Stud. 55(1), 23–40 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M.: Relevant alternatives and closure. Aust. J. Philos. 77(2), 196–208 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J.: Inquiry as Inquiry: A Logic of Scientific Discovery. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht (1999)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Holliday, W.H.: Epistemic logic, relevant alternatives and the dynamics of context. In: Lassiter, D., Slavkovic, M. (eds.) New Directions in Logic, Language and Computation. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 7415, pp. 109–129. Springer, Berlin/Heidelberg (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Holliday, W.H.: Epistemic closure and epistemic logic I: relevant alternatives and subjunctivism. J. Philos. Log. 44, 1–62 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holliday, W.H.: Fallibilism and multiple paths to knowledge. In: Gendler, T., Hawthorne, J. (eds.) Oxford Studies in Epistemology, vol. 5, pp. 97–144. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2015)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J.M.: A Treatise on Probability. Macmillan, London (1921)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S.: Nozick on knowledge. In: Philosophical Troubles: Collected Papers, vol. 1. Oxford University Press, New York (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S.: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd edn. (1st edn. published 1962). The University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1970)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawlor, K.: Assurance: An Austinian View of Knowledge and Knowledge Claims. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2013)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.: Relevant implication. Theoria 54(3), 161–174 (1988)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.: Elusive knowledge. Aust. J. Philos. 74(4), 549–567 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luper, S.: The epistemic predicament: knowledge, Nozickian track, and skepticism. Aust. J. Philos. 62, 26–50 (1984)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luper, S.: The Epistemic Closure Principle (2001). Substantive revision Wednesday 4 Aug 2010. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/closure-epistemic/

  • MacFarlane, J.: The assessment sensitivity of knowledge attributions. In: Gendler, T., Hawthorne, J. (eds.) Oxford Studies in Epistemology, vol. 1, pp. 197–234. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E.: Relevance Logic (1998). http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-relevance/. Substantive revision Mon 26 Mar 2012

  • Nozick, R.: Philosophical Explanations. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D.: Epistemological Disjunctivism. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2012)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J.: From contextualism to contrastivism. Philos. Stud. 119(1), 73–103 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J.: Contrastive knowledge. In: Gendler, T., Hawthorne, J. (eds.) Oxford Studies in Epistemology, vol. 1, pp. 235–271. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2005a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J.: What shifts? Thresholds, standards, or alternatives?. In: Preyer, G., Peter, G. (eds.) Contextualism in Philosophy, pp. 115–130. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2005b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J.: Closure, contrast, and answer. Philos. Stud. 133(2), 233–255 (2007a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J.: Knowing the answer. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 75(2), 383–403 (2007b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P.K.: Underdetermination of scientific theory (2009). http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scientific-underdetermination/. Substantive revision Mon 16 Sep 2013

  • Stanley, J.: Knowledge and Practical Interests. Oxford University Press, New York (2005)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P.: Ignorance: A Case for Skepticism. Oxford University Press, New York (1975)

    Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J.F.A.K.: Logical Dynamics of Information and Interaction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge/New York (2011)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J.: Are there counterexamples to the closure principle? In: Roth, M., Ross, G. (eds.) Doubting, pp. 13–27. Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht (1990)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J.: The new relevant alternatives theory. Philos. Perspect. 13, 155–180 (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S.: Aboutness. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2014)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L.: The inescapability of Gettier problems. Philos. Q. 44(174), 65–73 (1994)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Johan van Benthem and Krista Lawlor for much useful discussion during the development of material in this paper. Thanks for Chenwei Shi and an anonymous referee for many helpful comments based on a close reading of an earlier draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Hawke .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hawke, P. (2016). Relevant Alternatives in Epistemology and Logic. In: Redmond, J., Pombo Martins, O., Nepomuceno Fernández, Á. (eds) Epistemology, Knowledge and the Impact of Interaction. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 38. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26506-3_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics