Skip to main content

A Comparison of the Semantics of Natural Kind Terms and Artifactual Terms

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Epistemology, Knowledge and the Impact of Interaction

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 38))

  • 521 Accesses

Abstract

This paper aims to compare the semantics of natural kind terms and that of artifactual terms. To that end, we rely on the natural kind terms’ theory regarded as paradigmatic in contemporaneous semantics, the one put forward by Putnam, who sketched the extension of the semantics of natural kind terms to artifactual terms. In this paper we develop such extension concerning the reference of artifactual terms, although the reference fixing theory we advocate differs from that of Putnam’s. On the other hand, we propose a view on the meaning of these terms which conflicts with the one it would follow from extending to such terms Putnam’s view of meaning on natural kind terms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I will understand the expression “artifactual term” as interchangeable with “artifactual kind term” and consequently “artifact” with “artifactual kind”.

  2. 2.

    In (1973) Putnam distinguishes between physical magnitude terms and natural kind terms, although he claims that there are semantic similarities between both sorts of terms. In this paper I will not deal with physical magnitude terms.

  3. 3.

    See, for instance, Putnam (1975b, p. 231) and Putnam (1990, p. 58).

  4. 4.

    On these contributions see Putnam (1975b, pp. 227–234, 245, 265 and 271), as well as (1988), chapter 2.

  5. 5.

    Concerning the first procedure, see (1975b, pp. 225 and 229 ff.), and on the second, (1975b, pp. 229 f. and 232 f.).

  6. 6.

    I will speak of artifactual terms or artifactual kind terms – see note 1 above – instead of names of artifacts.

  7. 7.

    There is not a precise delimitation criterion for everyday artifactual terms, but the examples mentioned by Putnam are clear cases of them.

  8. 8.

    As it is well known, Kripke proposes in the second lecture of (1980) a theory of reference fixing for proper names that he extends in the third lecture to natural kind terms, according to which a term is introduced in an initial baptism in which its reference is fixed by ostension or “by a description” (Kripke 1980, pp. 96 f.). These procedures of reference fixing are similar to those proposed by Putnam concerning natural kind terms.

  9. 9.

    Putnam adds that the indexical description in question is uttered by “someone who is ‘focusing’ on a particular sample of substance” (Putnam 1988, p. 38). On this matter, Putnam asserts that he has taken the notion of “focusing” from Alan Berger; see Putnam (1988, pp. 33 and 130, n. 14). It is remarkable that although in that footnote 14 Putnam claims that Berger introduces the notion of “focusing” in Terms and Truth (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988), the published version of that book appeared later, that is, Berger (2002); thus, it is to be assumed that Putnam had access to a preliminary manuscript of that book. Concerning Berger’s notion of “focusing” see chapters 1 and 2 of Berger (2002).

  10. 10.

    Schwartz’s view in (1978) was somewhat different, since he claimed that “we can give an analytical specification in terms of form and function of what it is to be a member of the nominal kind” (Schwartz 1978, p. 572).

  11. 11.

    I say “descriptive-causal” instead of merely “descriptive” because of the causal component involved in the ostensive contact with members of the kind.

  12. 12.

    By the stereotype of an artifactual term there should be understood the properties that according to our common sense beliefs characterize the paradigmatic members of the artifactual kind. Concerning everyday artifacts every competent speaker in the use of the corresponding terms knows the intended function, the appearance and the manner of use of such artifacts. Although it should be recognized that the knowledge of their origin and features of their internal structure can be more imperfect, these are, as a rule, easily discernible.

  13. 13.

    The theory for reference borrowing put forward by Kripke in (1980) for proper names and natural kind terms is historical-causal.

  14. 14.

    Whereas not all artifacts are concrete entities, everyday artifacts are.

  15. 15.

    This is also a charge brought against Putnam’s thought experiment of Twin Earth in Putnam (1975b); see Burge (2013, p. 269 f.) and Putnam (2013, p. 274).

  16. 16.

    This paper has been supported by the Spanish Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness in the framework of the research project FFI2014-52244-P.

References

  • Abbott, B.: Nondescriptionality and natural kind terms. Linguist. Philos. 12, 269–291 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abbott, B.: Reference. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Baghramian, M. (ed.): Reading Putnam. Routledge, London/New York (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  • Berger, A.: Terms and Truth. Reference Direct and Anaphoric. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T.: Some remarks on ‘externalisms’. In: Baghramian (2013), pp. 263–271 (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M., Sterelny, K.: Language and Reality. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. 2nd ed., rev. and extended, 1st ed., 1987 (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  • Grandy, R.E.: Artifacts: parts and principles. In: Margolis, E., Laurence, S. (2007), pp. 18–32 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilpinen, R.: Artifact. In: Zalta, E.N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition) http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/artifact/ (2011)

  • Kornblith, H.: Referring to artifacts. Philos. Rev. 89, 109–114 (1980)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H.: How to refer to artifacts. In: Margolis, E., Laurence, S. (2007), pp. 138–149 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K.: The Structure of Objects. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2008)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S.: Naming and Necessity. Blackwell, Oxford (1980)

    Google Scholar 

  • LaPorte, J.: Natural Kinds and Conceptual Change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  • Losonsky, M.: The nature of artifacts. Philosophy 65, 81–88 (1990)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E., Laurence, S. (eds.): Creations of the Mind. Theories of Artifacts and Their Representation. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, J.A.: Schwartz on reference. South. J. Philos. 20, 359–365 (1982)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: Is semantics possible? In: Kiefer, H., Munitz, M. (eds.) Languages, Belief and Metaphysics. State University of New York Press, New York. Reprinted in Putnam (1975a), pp. 139–152 (1970)

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: Explanation and reference. In: Pearce, G., Maynard, P. (eds.) Conceptual Change. Reidel, Dordrecht. Reprinted in Putnam (1975a), pp. 196–214 (1973)

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: Mind, Language and Reality. Philosophical papers, vol. 2. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1975a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: The meaning of ‘meaning’. In: Putnam (1975a), pp. 215–271 (1975b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: Realism and Reason. Philosophical papers, vol. 3. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: Meaning holism and epistemic holism. In: Cramer, K., et al. (eds.) Theorie der Subjektivität, pp. 251–277. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: Representation and Reality. MIT Press, Cambridge (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: Realism with a Human Face. (Edited and with introduction by J. Conant). Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: Comments on Tyler Burge. In: Baghramian (2013), pp. 272–274 (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S.P.: Putnam on artifacts. Philos. Rev. 87, 566–574 (1978)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S.P.: Natural kinds and nominal kinds. Mind 89, 182–195 (1980)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S.P.: Reply to Kornblith and Nelson. South. J. Philos. 21, 475–479 (1983)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soavi, M.: Realism, Antirealism and Artefact Kinds. CLEP, Padova (2009)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luis Fernández Moreno .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Fernández Moreno, L. (2016). A Comparison of the Semantics of Natural Kind Terms and Artifactual Terms. In: Redmond, J., Pombo Martins, O., Nepomuceno Fernández, Á. (eds) Epistemology, Knowledge and the Impact of Interaction. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 38. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26506-3_23

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics