Skip to main content

The Quest for the Concept in the Twentieth Century: Predicates, Functions, Categories and Argument Structure

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 523 Accesses

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 38))

Abstract

Philosophers, logicians, linguists and even mathematicians have tried to decipher the mechanisms by which concepts are constructed from the meaning of words. One way to achieve this was the study of lexical meaning and its combinatorial properties. Our purpose is to explore the seminal ideas that have resulted in categorial grammars and their relationship with other grammatical models and actual theories of meaning, in a historical process that takes us from the notion of category to that of predication, and from this to the notion of function, then to functional categories and finally to the linguistic notion of argument structure.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Functional and morphosyntactic categories that reach the Roman grammarians—and from them the early modern period—are those proposed by the Alexandrian, who in turn adapted the categories proposed by the Stoic school. The Stoics used a semantic criterion for the classification of the parts of speech, following the Aristotelian style, but they introduced functional changes based on the morphology of words. So, they made a distinction in Aristotle’s syndesmoi between a group of words with inflection that they called arthra (pronouns and articles), and the invariable words (prepositions and conjunctions); they also created the category of adverbs (mesotes) based on syntactic criteria—adverbs appear combined with the verb—as well as morphological ones—adverbs are formed on nominal or adjectival themes and roots. Finally, Stoics introduced the concept of klisis to denote the grammatical variation of a word, limiting the aristotelian notion of case (ptosis) to the words of nominal category (proper names, common nouns and adjectives) as well as to the words classified as arthra (pronouns and articles), this being the basis for the distinction between these categories and verbs (rhema). A more extensive description of the topic can be found at Robins (1969).

  2. 2.

    Among them we can highlight Martin of Dacia, Michel de Marbais, Peter Helias and Thomas of Erfurt. The philosophy of the Modistae drank directly from the work of Aristotle, but also had the probable influence of commentators such as Duns Scotus. Their theories were also clearly related to those of other philosophers of the period as Roger Bacon or William of Ockham.

  3. 3.

    Leibniz’s proposal was very important and influential on the search for universal languages during the eighteenth Century, as well as were his etymological studies on the rise of comparative linguistics at the nineteenth Century.

  4. 4.

    Although this principle is traditionally attributed to Frege, was not he who formulated it, but Rudolf Carnap, who ascribed him the following principles of interchangeability: “First principle […] the nominatum of the whole expression is a function of the nominata of the names occurring in it. […] Second principle […] the sense of the whole expression is a function of the senses of the names occurring in it.” (Carnap 1947: 121). Later, Donald Davidson spread the idea that the Principle of Compositionality is due to the distinction between meaning and reference in Frege: “If we want a theory that gives us the meaning (as distinct from reference) of each sentence, we must start with the meaning (as distinct from reference) of the parts. Up to now we have been following Frege’s footsteps; thanks to him the path is well known and even well worn.” (Davidson 1967: 306).

  5. 5.

    This is the real Frege’s Principle, which was set by him in The Foundations of Arithmetic: “Mann muss die Wörter im Sätze betrachten, wenn man nach ihrer Bedeutung fragt […] Es genügt, wenn der Satz als Ganzes einen Sinn hat; dadurch erhalten auch seine Teile ihren Inhalt.” (Frege 1884: secc. 60).

  6. 6.

    Frege’s idea of replacing the subject-predicate structure by the function-argument structure as a representation of the enunciative sentence was fundamental to the development of the theory of types and Russell’s proposal of a hierarchy of types to solve the so-called Frege’s paradox. Russell’s theory of types influenced Lesniewski’s grammar of semantic categories, but it was more appropriate for formal languages than for natural languages. However, it was Husserl’s theory of a pure grammar which served as a model for Ajdukiewicz’s notion of a logical syntax of natural language because of its more natural conception of semantic categories.

  7. 7.

    In linguistics, the function of adjectives in a Noun Phrase can be interpreted as a restriction of the reference of the nouns they modify, whereas determiners select a subset of the reference of nouns.

  8. 8.

    The correspondence between sentence constituents in a phrase structure grammar and the categorial types proposed by Montague can be easily established from the syntactic functions and the generic meaning attributed to the different parts of speech (Montague 1973/1974: 249–250).

  9. 9.

    The relationship between predicates and arguments depends on the valence of the latter. It was first expressed by the French linguist Lucien Tesnière, for whom an argument is an expression that helps complete the meaning of the predicate (Tesnière 1959[1965]: 128).

References

  • Ajdukiewicz, K.: Die syntaktische Konnexität. Studia Philosophica 1, 1–27 (1935)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Hillel, Y.: On syntactical categories. J. Symb. Log. 15, 1–16 (1950)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Hillel, Y.: A quasi-arithmetical notation for syntactic description. Language XXIX, 47–58 (1953)

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvin, W.H., Bickerton, D.: Lingua ex Machina. Reconciling Darwin and Chomsky with the Human Brain. MIT, Cambridge (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R.: Meaning and Necessity. Chicago University Press, Chicago (1947)

    Google Scholar 

  • Casadio, C.: Semantic categories and the development of categorial grammars. In: Oehrle, R., Bach, E., Wheeler, D. (eds.) Categorial Grammars and Natural Language Structures, pp. 125–151. Reidel, Dordrecht (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R.: Type theory with records and unification-based grammar. In: Hamm, F., Kepser, S. (eds.) Logics for Linguistic Structures, pp. 9–34. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D.: Truth and meaning. Synthese 17, 304–323 (1967)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D.R., Wall, R.E., Peters, S.: Introduction to Montague semantics. Reidel, Dordrecht (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G.: Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Eine logisch mathematische Untersuchung über den Begriff der Zahl. Wilhelm Koebner, Breslau (1884)

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J., Stokhof, M.: Dynamic montague grammar. In: Papers from the Second Symposium on Logic and Language, pp. 3–48. Akademiai Kiadoo (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J., Stokhof, M.: Dynamic predicate logic. Linguist. Philos. 14, 39–100 (1991)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E.: Logische Untersuchungen. Niemeyer, Halle (1990–1901)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kanerva, P.: Sparse Distributed Memory. MIT, Cambridge (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lambek, J.: The mathematics of sentence structure. Am. Math. Mon. 65(3), 154–170 (1958). Reprinted in Buszkowski, W., Marciszewski, W., van Benthem, J. (eds.) Categorial Grammar, pp. 153–172. John Benjamins, Amsterdam (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lesniewski, S.: O podstawach matematyki. Przeglad Filozoficzny 30, 164–206 (1927–1931); 31, 261–291 (1928); 32, 60–101 (1929); 33, 77–105 (1930); 34, 142–170 (1931)

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R.: The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary english. In: Thomason, R. (ed.) Formal Philosophy: Selected Papers of Richard Montague, pp. 247–270. Yale University Press, New Haven (1973/1974)

    Google Scholar 

  • Pentus, M.: Lambek Calculus and Formal Grammars, American Mathematical Society. (Transl. from the original Ph.D. Dissertation, Moscow State University (1997/1996))

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollard, C., Sag, I.: Head-driven Phrase Structure Grammar. Center for the Study of Language and Information (CSLI) Lecture Notes. Stanford University Press/University of Chicago Press, Stanford (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Robins, R.H.: A short History of Linguistics. Longman, London (1969)

    Google Scholar 

  • Sigman, M., Cecchi, G.A.: Global organization of the wordnet lexicon. PNAS 99(3), 1742–1747 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sikkel, K., Nijholt, A.: Parsing of context-free languages. In: Rozenberg, G., Salomaa, A. (eds.) The Handbook of Formal Languages, vol. II, pp. 61–100. Springer, Berlin (1997)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tesnière, L.: Éléments de syntaxe structurale. Klincksieck, Paris (1959); 2nd edition (1965)

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorndike, E.L., Woodworth, R.S.: The influence of improvement in one mental function upon the efficiency of other functions. Psychol. Rev. 8, 247–261, 384–395, 553–564 (1901)

    Google Scholar 

  • Uszkoreit, H.: Categorial unification grammars. In: Proceedings of the 11th International Conference on Computational Linguistics. ACL, Bonn (1986)

    Google Scholar 

  • Villavicencio, A.: The acquisition of a unification-based generalised categorial grammar. Technical report 533, UCAM Computer Laboratory, Cambridge (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  • Whorf, B.L.: Language, Thought and Reality. Selected Writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf. MIT, Cambridge (1956)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper is part of the research project “Awareness, Logic and Computation”, financed by the Government of Spain. I would also like to acknowledge all the help and support of the members of the Research Group on Logic, Language and Information at the University of Seville (GILLIUS), as well as the suggestions of an anonymous referee that have been very helpful to improve the original text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Francisco J. Salguero-Lamillar .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Salguero-Lamillar, F.J. (2016). The Quest for the Concept in the Twentieth Century: Predicates, Functions, Categories and Argument Structure. In: Redmond, J., Pombo Martins, O., Nepomuceno Fernández, Á. (eds) Epistemology, Knowledge and the Impact of Interaction. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 38. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26506-3_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics