Skip to main content

Ascribing Knowledge to Experts: A Virtue-Contextualist Approach

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Epistemology, Knowledge and the Impact of Interaction

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 38))

  • 518 Accesses

Abstract

I argue that epistemic contextualism, as conceived by Lewis and DeRose, cannot accommodate knowledge-ascribing behavior in contexts where expert counsel is sought. Narrowly focusing on the subject’s epistemic position with respect to p in ∼p possibilities yields the wrong verdict in such cases. To account for our judgments, I propose that contextualists should look to virtue responsibilism, which founds epistemic evaluation both on the mastery of relevant underlying principles and their explicit and implicit application. Such assessment is not measured by S’s ability to rule out relevant alternatives or track the truth of p, and for this reason, is not captured by either version of contextualism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Take for example, Matt McGrath’s train cases in “Evidence, Pragmatics and Justification,” Philosophical Review 111, no. 1 (2002): 67–94. Stewart Cohen’s airport cases in “Contextualism, Skepticism and The Structure of Reasons,” Philosophical Perspectives 13: Epistemology, ed. James E. Tomberlin (Atascadero: Ridgeway, 1999): 57–89.

  2. 2.

    Keith DeRose, “Contextualism and Knowledge Attributions” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52, no. 4 (December 1992): 913–929.

  3. 3.

    Invariantists offer an alternative explanation according to which the standards of knowledge remain fixed, but what is communicated varies from one context to the next. See, for example, Patrick Rysiew, “The Context-Sensitivity of Knowledge Attributions”. I will not be discussing this view here as my objective is to present and suggest a possible solution for problems internal to contextualism.

  4. 4.

    David Lewis, “Elusive Knowledge,” in Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader, eds. Keith DeRose and Ted Warfield (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999): 225.

  5. 5.

    Fred Dretske, “The Pragmatic Dimension of Knowledge,” Philosophical Studies 40, no. 3. (Nov., 1981): 370–1.

  6. 6.

    Keith DeRose, “Solving the Skeptical Problem,” in Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader, eds. Keith DeRose and Ted Warfield (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999): 206.

  7. 7.

    See discussion in Duncan Pritchard, “Virtue Epistemology and the Acquisition of Knowledge,” Philosophical Explorations 8, no. 3 (September 2005): 229–243.

  8. 8.

    I am not here defending a virtue-theoretic analysis of knowledge, but rather suggesting that contextualists broaden their view to incorporate virtues as significant to knowledge ascriptions. This is because I accept the basic contextualist thesis that knowledge standards will vary and it is not clear that virtues will be relevant to identifying knowers in all contexts. For a different view, see Christopher Hookway, “How to be a Virtue Epistemologist,” in Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology, eds. Michael DePaul and Linda Zagzebski. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003): 183–202.) Hookway suggests that the central focus of epistemology move towards an examination of the deliberative process, rather than the analysis of the static cognitive states of justified belief and knowledge. He discusses virtues not as an element of knowledge, but rather as relevant to epistemic evaluation outside of this focus.

  9. 9.

    Zagzebski, Linda. Virtues of the Mind. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).

  10. 10.

    Zagzebski, 177.

  11. 11.

    Christopher Hookway, “Epistemic Norms and Theoretical Deliberation” Ratio 22 (December 1999): 380–397. Hookway also discusses negative norms of deliberation in his “Epistemic Akrasia and Epistemic Virtue” in Virtue Epistemology: Essays on Epistemic Virtue and Responsibility, eds. Linda Zagzebski and Abrol Fairweather (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001): 178–199.

  12. 12.

    Hookway, “Epistemic Norms” 386.

  13. 13.

    Ibid., 392.

  14. 14.

    Hookway, “How to be a Virtue Epistemologist” 187.

  15. 15.

    Indeed, Bonjour attempts to include the input of observation states, but maintains that they do not provide justification for resulting perceptual beliefs. Laurence BonJour, The Structure of Empirical Knowledge (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985), chapter 6.

  16. 16.

    Pritchard, “Virtue Epistemology and the Acquisition of Knowledge”.

References

  • BonJour, L.: The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1985)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S.: Contextualism, skepticism and the structure of reasons. In: Tomberlin, J.E. (ed.) Philosophical Perspectives 13: Epistemology, pp. 57–89. Ridgeway, Atascadero (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K.: Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 52(4), 913–929 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K.: Solving the skeptical problem. In: Keith, D.R., Ted, W. (eds.) Skepticism: a contemporary reader, p. 206. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F.: The pragmatic dimensions of knowledge. Philos. Stud. 40(3), 363–378 (1981)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hookway, C.: Epistemic norms and theoretical deliberation. Ratio 22, 380–397 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hookway, C.: Epistemic Akrasia and epistemic virtue. In: Zagzebski, L. (ed.) Virtue Epistemology: Essays on Epistemic Virtue and Responsibility. Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hookway, C.: How to be a virtue epistemologist. In: DePaul, M., Zagzebski, L. (eds.) Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology, pp. 183–202. Oxford University Press, New York (2003)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.: Elusive knowledge. In: DeRose, K., Warfield, T. (eds.) Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader, pp. 220–238. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M.: Evidence, pragmatics and justification. Philos. Rev. 111(1), 67–94 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D.: Virtue epistemology and the acquisition of knowledge. Philos. Explor. 8(3), 229–243 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L.: Virtues of the Mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1996)

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sruthi Rothenfluch Ph.D. .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rothenfluch, S. (2016). Ascribing Knowledge to Experts: A Virtue-Contextualist Approach. In: Redmond, J., Pombo Martins, O., Nepomuceno Fernández, Á. (eds) Epistemology, Knowledge and the Impact of Interaction. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 38. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26506-3_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics