Advertisement

Representational Development Need Not Be Explicable-By-Content

  • Nicholas SheaEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 376)

Abstract

Fodor’s radical concept nativism flowed from his view that hypothesis testing is the only route to concept acquisition. Many have successfully objected to the overly-narrow restriction to learning by hypothesis testing. Existing representations can be connected to a new representational vehicle so as to constitute a sustaining mechanism for the new representation, without the new representation thereby being constituted by or structured out of the old. This paper argues that there is also a deeper objection. Connectionism shows that a more fundamental assumption underpinning the debate can also be rejected: the assumption that the development of a new representation must be explained in content-involving terms if innateness is to be avoided.

Fodor has argued that connectionism offers no new resources to explain concept acquisition: unless it is merely an uninteresting claim about neural implementation, connectionism’s defining commitment to distributed representations reduces to the claim that some representations are structured out of others (which is the old, problematic research programme). Examination of examples of representational development in connectionist networks shows, however, that some such models explain the development of new representational capacities in non-representational terms. They illustrate the possibility of representational development that is not explicable-by-content. Connectionist representations can be distributed in an important sense, which is incompatible with the assumption of explanation-by-content: they can be distributed over non-representational resources that account for their development. Rejecting the assumption of explanation-by-content thereby opens up a more radical way of rejecting Fodor’s argument for radical concept nativism.

Keywords

Conceptual development Nativism Connectionism Parallel distributed processing Representational development 

Notes

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank the follow for generous comments: David Braddon-Mitchell, Steve Butterfill, Nick Chater, Martin Davies, Jerry Fodor, Paul Griffiths, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Richard Holton, Matteo Mameli, David Papineau, Gualtiero Piccinini, Kim Plunkett, Paul Smolensky, Mark Sprevak, Scott Sturgeon; the referees and audiences in Melbourne, Oxford and Sydney.

References

  1. Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford/New York: O.U.P.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Chalmers, D. (1992). Subsymbolic computation and the Chinese room. In J. Dinsmore (Ed.), The symbolic and connectionist paradigms: Closing the gap. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  3. Churchland, P. M. (1998). Conceptual similarity across sensory and neural diversity: The Fodor/Lepore challenge answered. Journal of Philosophy, 95(1), 5–32.Google Scholar
  4. Churchland, P. M. (2012). Plato’s camera: How the physical brain captures a landscape of abstract universals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  6. Clark, A. (2001). Mindware. Oxford: O.U.P.Google Scholar
  7. Cowie, F. (1999). What’s within? Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  8. Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behaviour: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. London/Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  10. Fodor, J. A. (1981). The present status of the innateness controversy. In Representations: Philosophical essays on the foundations of cognitive science. London/Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  11. Fodor, J. A. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  12. Fodor, J. A. (1994). The elm and the expert. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.Google Scholar
  13. Fodor, J. A. (1998). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. New York: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Fodor, J. A. (2001). Doing without what’s within: Fiona Cowie’s critique of nativism. Mind, 110, 99–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Fodor, J. A. (2004). Distributed representations; enough already. http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/courses/representation/papers/fodordistributed.pdf. Accessed 2 Jun 2014.
  16. Fodor, J. A. (2007). The revenge of the given. In McLaughlin & Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  17. Fodor, J. A. (2008). LOT 2: The language of thought revisited. Oxford/New York: O.U.P.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Fodor, J. A., & Lepore, E. (1992). Holism: A shopper’s guide. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  19. Fodor, J. A., & Lepore, E. (1999). All at sea in semantic space: Churchland on meaning similarity. Journal of Philosophy, 96(8), 381–403.Google Scholar
  20. Fodor, J. A., & McLaughlin, B. (1990). Connectionism and the problem of systematicity: Why Smolensky’s solution doesn’t work. Cognition, 35, 183–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition, 28, 3–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Johnson, M. H., et al. (1991). Newborns’ preferential tracking of face-like stimuli and its subsequent decline. Cognition, 40, 1–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Laakso, A., & Cottrell, G. (2000). Content and cluster analysis: Assessing representational similarity in neural systems. Philosophical Psychology, 13(1), 47–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (2002). Radical concept nativism. Cognition, 86, 25–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Macnamara, J. (1986). Border dispute: The place of logic in psychology. Oxford/New York: O.U.P.Google Scholar
  26. Mameli, M. (2008). On innateness: The clutter hypothesis and the cluster hypothesis. Journal of Philosophy, 55, 719–736.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Mareschal, D., & Schultz, T. R. (1996). Generative connectionist networks and constructivist cognitive development. Cognitive Development, 11, 571–603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Margolis, E. (1998). How to acquire a concept. Mind & Language, 13(3), 347–369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. McLeod, P., Shallice, T., & Plaut, D. C. (2000). Attractor dynamics in word recognition: Converging evidence from errors by normal subjects, dyslexic patients and a connectionist model. Cognition, 74, 91–113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  31. Morton, J., & Johnson, M. H. (1991). CONSPEC and CONLEARN: A two process theory of infant face recognition. Psychological Review, 98, 164–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Papineau, D. (1987). Reality and representation. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  33. Plunkett, K., & Sinha, C. (1992). Connectionism and developmental theory. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 10(3), 209–254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Quartz, S. R., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1997). The neural basis of cognitive development: A constructivist manifesto. Behavioral & Brain Sciences, 20, 537–596.Google Scholar
  35. Quillian, M. R. (1967). Word concepts: A theory and simulation of some basic semantic capabilities. Behavioral Science, 12(5), 410–430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Rolls, E., & Treves, A. (1998). Neural networks and brain function. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  37. Rupert, R. D. (1998). On the relationship between naturalistic semantics and individuation criteria for terms in a language of thought. Synthese, 117(1), 95–131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Rupert, R. (2001). Coining terms in the language of thought. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 499–530.Google Scholar
  39. Ryder, D. (2004). SINBAD neurosemantics: A theory of mental representation. Mind & Language, 19(2), 211–240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Samuels, R. (2002). Nativism in cognitive science. Mind & Language, 17, 233–265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Sejnowski, T., & Rosenberg, C. (1987). Parallel networks that learn to pronounce English text. Complex Systems, 1, 145–168.Google Scholar
  42. Shea, N. (2007a). Consumers need information: Supplementing teleosemantics with an input condition. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75(2), 404–435.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Shea, N. (2007b). Content and its vehicles in connectionist systems. Mind & Language, 22(3), 246–269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Shea, N. (2011). New concepts can be learned, review essay on Susan Carey. The Origin of Concepts. Biology & Philosophy, 26, 129–139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Shea, N. (2012a). Genetic representation explains the cluster of innateness-related properties. Mind & Language, 27(4), 466–493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Shea, N. (2012b). New thinking, innateness and inherited representation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 367, 2234–2244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Strevens, M. (2012). Theoretical terms without analytic truths. Philosophical Studies, 160(1), 167–190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Tiffany, E. (1999). Semantics San Diego style. Journal of Philosophy, 96, 416–429.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.King’s College LondonLondonUK

Personalised recommendations