Skip to main content

Feminist and Non-feminist Philosophy of Biology: Parallels, Differences, and Prospects for Future Engagements

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 317))

Abstract

I identify several substantive parallels in the issues of interest, and methodological and conceptual frameworks employed, in the research traditions of feminist and non-feminist philosophy of biology. I also identify several substantive differences in the emphases of the two traditions, including that biological research and hypotheses focusing on sex and gender raise political and ethical issues that non-feminist philosophers of biology rarely address. I conclude that a growing interest in philosophy of science in promoting “socially responsible science”, and engaging in “socially relevant” and “socially responsible” philosophy of science, should make it possible for the traditions to more fruitfully engage one another.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There are exceptions. See, e.g., Hubbard (1983).

  2. 2.

    Although the distinction is not without its problems or its critics, I use “sex” to refer to females and males (typically defined by biologists on the basis of their gametes) and “gender” to refer to non-biological characteristics associated with females and males, including women and men: characteristics construed to be “feminine” or “masculine,” including behaviors, temperaments, cognitive predispositions, roles, and so forth. Feminists drew and insisted on the distinction early on in the Second Wave of the Women’s Movement and it was brought to bear by feminist scientists and science scholars beginning in the 1970s critical of and/or attempting to “disrupt” and/or “replace” the conflation of the two in scientific theorizing in the social and biological sciences.

  3. 3.

    I return to this issue in the concluding section.

  4. 4.

    For example, feminists also cite commitments to uni-directional and “hierarchical” models of causal processes, represented, for example, in Francis Cricks’ “Central Dogma” and in models of hormonal effects on behavior in behavioral endocrinology, as an example of how historically-specific views of what constitutes “serious science” impact scientific reasoning. There are stronger versions of contextualism in feminist philosophy of science, including standpoint theory and arguments for the situatedness and partial perspectives of all inquirers (e.g., as advocated, respectively, in Harding 1986 and Haraway 1988).

  5. 5.

    One focus of feminist critiques of the models under discussion, and of research in reproductive and neuro endocrinology next discussed, is the assumption of sexual dimorphism. This is beyond the scope of the current discussion, but see Fausto-Sterling (1985/1992).

  6. 6.

    I emphasize unrecognized and unwitting bias because cases in which scientists (or others) deliberately manipulate research questions, hypotheses, or tests on the basis of bias, are, from an epistemological point of view, uninteresting.

  7. 7.

    As discussed in the next section, metaphors are abundant in the biological sciences—and some argue in science generally. One major problem arises when scientists don’t recognize the metaphors they invoke as metaphors. Altmann was specific that her notion of “budgeting” is a metaphor.

  8. 8.

    Anderson is not the first to argue for “evaluatively-thick concepts.” She is the first to find such concepts at work in science and to provide a feminist analysis of their role and consequences.

References

  • Anderson, E. (2004). Uses of value judgments in science: A general argument, with lessons from a case study of feminist research on divorce. Hypatia, 19(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biology and Gender Study Group. (1989). The importance of feminist critique for contemporary cell biology. In N. Tuana (Ed.), Feminism and science (pp. 172–187). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bleier, R. (1984). Science and gender: A critique of biology and its theories on women. Elmsford, NY: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bleier, R. (Ed.). (1986). Feminist approaches to science. New York: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buller, D. (2005). Adapting minds: Evolutionary psychology and the persistent quest for human nature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. (2004). Evolutionary psychology: The new science of the mind. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1871). The descent of man and selection in relation to sex. London: John Murray.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Drea, C., & Wallen, K. (2003). Female sexuality and the myth of male control. In C. Travis (Ed.), Evolution, gender, and rape. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fausto-Sterling, A. (1985/1992). Myths of gender: Biological theories about women and men. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, C. (2004). Feminism and science: Mechanism without reductionism. National Women’s Studies Association Journal, 16, 136–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, C. (2011). Feminist philosophy of biology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/feminist-philosophy-biology. Accessed Jan 5, 2015.

  • Fehr, C., & Plaisance, K. (2010). Making philosophy of science more socially relevant: An introduction. Synthese, 177(3), 301–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S., & Rader, K. (2001). Revisiting women, gender, and feminism in developmental biology. In A. Creager, E. Lunbeck, & L. Schiebinger (Eds.), Feminism in twentieth-century science, technology and medicine (pp. 73–97). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (1993). Epistemological reflections of an old feminist. Reason Papers, 18, 31–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. (1988). Situated knowledges: The science question in feminism and the privilege of partial perspective. Feminist Studies, 14, 575–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. (1989). Primate visions: Gender, race, and nature in the world of modern science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, S. (1986). The science question in feminism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hrdy, S. B. (1986). Empathy, polyandry, and the myth of the coy female. In R. Bleier (Ed.), Feminist approaches to science (pp. 119–146). New York: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubbard, R. (1983). Have only men evolved? In S. Harding & M. Hintikka (Eds.), Discovering reality: Feminist perspectives on epistemology, metaphysics, methodology, and philosophy of science (pp. 45–70). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, J. (2010). When socially determined categories make biological realities: Understanding black/white health disparities. Monist, 93(2), 283–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (1985). Reflections on gender and science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). 1953 and all that: A tale of two sciences. The Philosophical Review, 93(3), 335–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1985). Vaulting ambition: Sociobiology and the quest for human nature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1996). The lives to come: The genetic revolution and human possibilities. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (1993). Biology as ideology: The doctrine of DNA. New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. A. (1994). The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. A. (2005). Why the gene will not return. Philosophy of Science, 72, 287–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, E. (1991). The egg and the sperm: How science has constructed a romance based on stereotypical male-female roles. Signs, 16, 485–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, L. H. (1990). Who knows: From Quine to feminist empiricism. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, L. H. (2003). The descent of evolutionary explanations: Darwinian vestiges in the social sciences. In S. P. Turner & P. A. Roth (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of the special sciences (pp. 258–290). London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, L. H. & Wylie, A. (2004). Special issue of hypatia on feminism and science. Hypatia, 19(1).

    Google Scholar 

  • Okruhlik, K. (2004). Logical empiricism, feminism, and Neurath’s auxiliary motive. Hypatia, 19(1), 48–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinnick, C., Koertge, N., & Almeder, R. (Eds.). (2003). Scrutinizing feminist epistemology: An examination of gender in science. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, R. (2007). Evolutionary psychology as maladapted psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2008). Darwinism and its discontents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2013). The Gaia hypothesis: Science on a pagan planet. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schiebinger, L. (1999). Has feminism changed science?. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (Ed.). (2006). Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology (3rd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E., & Wilson, D. S. (1999). Unto others: The evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, H. G., & Masters, J. C. (1992). Sexual selection: Contemporary debates. In E. F. Keller & E. A. Lloyd (Eds.), Keywords in evolutionary biology (pp. 294–301). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornhill, R., & Palmer, C. (2000). A natural history of rape. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vickers, A. L., & Kitcher, P. (2003). Popsociobiology reborn: The evolutionary psychology of sex and violence. In C. Travis (Ed.), Evolution, gender, and rape (pp. 139–168). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O. (1975). Sociobiology: The new synthesis. Boston: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M., & Daly, M. (1998). Lethal and nonlethal violence against wives and the evolutionary psychology of male sexual proprietariness. In R. E. Dobash & R. P. Dobash (Eds.), Violence against women: International and cross-disciplinary perspectives (pp. 199–230). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lynn Hankinson-Nelson .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hankinson-Nelson, L. (2016). Feminist and Non-feminist Philosophy of Biology: Parallels, Differences, and Prospects for Future Engagements. In: Amoretti, M., Vassallo, N. (eds) Meta-Philosophical Reflection on Feminist Philosophies of Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 317. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26348-9_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics