Skip to main content

New Debates in Old Ethical Skins

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Ethics of Science and Technology Assessment ((ETHICSSCI,volume 44))

Abstract

One of the central characteristics of modern science is that understanding can be measured by prediction, manipulation, and manufacture. That is why synthetic biology can be regarded as the climax of this project. It would seem that we truly understand living organisms only when we can re-create them. Synthetic biology therefore radicalizes tendencies in modern science. What does this mean for ethics? By applying five criteria, originally proposed by Hans Jonas, we can show that synthetic biology is of high ethical relevance. To illustrate this relevance, traditional ethical issues, such as risk and outcome-uncertainty, are applied. The ‘playing God’ argument is scrutinized by dividing it into three sub-arguments: the ‘hubris’ argument (science overestimates its power), the ‘taboo’ argument (some things should not be done at all), and the ‘sorcerer’s apprentice’ argument (we might not be able to control what we create). None of these concerns are entirely new; they are known, for example, in genetic engineering. But they seem to reach new significance in the realm of synthetic biology. As a consequence, precautionary principles are most certainly demanded by synthetic biology and a new ethical debate is called for. This debate is urgent but also particularly challenging. It raises fundamental issues (such as the meaning of basic terms like ‘nature’) and faces professional, conceptual, and institutional inhibitions which must be overcome for substantial answers to be reached. The chapter concludes by suggesting three ethical laws which might be taken as basic for any future ethics of synthetic biology. 1.: A biotic artefact may not injure a human being. 2.: A biotic artefact must be strictly functional, except where this would conflict with 1. And 3.: A biotic artefact must be protected and respected as a form of life, so long as such protection does not conflict with either 1 or 2.

I would feel more optimistic about a bright future for man

if he spent less time proving that he can outwit Nature

and more time tasting her sweetness and respecting her seniority.

E.B. White (2007)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The Vietnam War, for example, triggered an intense debate on the use of power, just war, and just society. Rawls’ Theory of Justice (1971) can be read as a response to this event.

  2. 2.

    A general awareness of environmental impact began earlier, with, for example, Rachel’ Carson’s Silent Spring (1962) and the studies of the Club of Rome.

  3. 3.

    This is captured by Hegel’s melancholic remark in the Preface of his Philosophy of Right (1820): “the owl of Minerva spreads its wings only with the falling of the dusk”.

  4. 4.

    At the same time, the general acceptance of modern technology declined and mistrust and disapproval (for example, of nuclear power) became quite common in the West (e.g. Habermas, Marcuse, Schelsky, but also Pardo and Hagen in this volume): “Without this crisis [of orientation] surrounding the optimistic belief in progress, TA would presumably never have developed” (Grunwald 2009, p. 1105). The pressure became too high and politics realized that it had to find answers—which required a more detailed knowledge and understanding of the societal and environmental impacts of concrete technical products and processes (TA), and of the probability and severity of possible damage (RA).

  5. 5.

    The “book” of the universe “is written in the mathematical language” as Galilei remarked in 1623 (1842, p.171). Quoted from Donald DeMarco (1986).

  6. 6.

    It is not a sufficient condition because we can sometimes make things which we do not understand.

  7. 7.

    Cf. Press release from the J. Craig Ventre Institute (20th May 2010): “they designed and inserted into the genome what they called watermarks. These are specifically designed segments of DNA that use the “alphabet” of genes and proteins that enable the researcher to spell out words and phrases. […] Encoded in the watermarks is a new DNA code for writing words, sentences and numbers. In addition to the new code there is a web address to send emails to if you can successfully decode the new code, the names of 46 authors and other key contributors and three quotations: ‘TO LIVE, TO ERR, TO FALL, TO TRIUMPH, TO RECREATE LIFE OUT OF LIFE.’—JAMES JOYCE; ‘SEE THINGS NOT AS THEY ARE, BUT AS THEY MIGHT BE.’—a quote from the book, ‘American Prometheus’; ‘WHAT I CANNOT BUILD (sic!), I CANNOT UNDERSTAND.’—RICHARD FEYNMAN.” See: http://www.jcvi.org/cms/press/press-releases/full-text/article/first-self-replicating-synthetic-bacterial-cell-constructed-by-j-craig-venter-institute-researcher/#sthash.DPPZiRxd.dpuf.

  8. 8.

    This is not true for all sciences. Astronomy, for example, has long been considered to be a science without being able to perform any experiments. Here, the predictive power of theories replaces the need to bring about effects.

  9. 9.

    Meditationes sacrae 1597, 11th section, “De Haeresibus”, quoted from Bacon 1711, p. 402.

  10. 10.

    Experiments with bacteria such as E. coli can take less time. It is therefore mainly with bacteria that evolutionary experiments are performed.

  11. 11.

    One might object that domestication and breeding are already a “craft-based technology” that “was used in transforming living organisms to become biotic artefacts” (Lee 2009, p. 101). But genetic engineering is much more efficient and systematic, and allows for conscious intervention into life-forms.

  12. 12.

    This is a one-sided ambivalence; he does not explore the possibility that bad intent might ultimately have good consequences.

  13. 13.

    Testifying in his defense in his 1954 security hearings (p. 81 of the official transcript)

    Quoted from http://en.wikiquote.org/wiki/Robert_Oppenheimer (20.7.2013).

  14. 14.

    For general metaphysical questions raised by technology see also Dupuy (2009, p. 214).

  15. 15.

    Or perhaps even of other planets: “One thing that was agreed upon, however, is the tremendous excitement and potential for synthetic biology to positively transform humanity in the coming years”, as the Stanford-Brown iGEM team says, a group working at BioBricks parts which allow cells to survive harsh extraterrestrial conditions (Biobricks are defined DNA sequences with a known function). Brown-Stanford iGEM 2011 (http://2011.igem.org/Team:Brown Stanford/SynEthics/Summary).

  16. 16.

    When Craig Venter’s group first made a synthetic bacterial genome, announced as the “First Self-Replicating Synthetic Bacterial Cell” (Press Release 20-May-2010), this achievement (and the way in which it was presented) stirred a debate on ‘life’. Speculations on the metaphysical (and theological) implications of creating life followed (see, for example, the Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethics, 2010).

  17. 17.

    Perhaps not even for genetic engineering (see Block 2012).

  18. 18.

    There are other products occasionally discussed in literature (Church and Regis 2012): transgenic “Glofish” with a fluorescent colour from a jelly fish, and goats which have a spider-gene so that spider silk can be extracted from their milk. These, however, are not proper examples of synthetic biology; they are not new, but only genetically modified life-forms.

  19. 19.

    Consisting of the Action Group on Erosion, Technology and Concentration (ETC Group), Center for Food Safety Center for Food Safety Econexus, Friends of the Earth USA, International Center for Technology Assessment, and The Sustainability Council of New Zealand. Cf. http://www.econexus.info/sites/econexus/files/CSOsynbiosubmission_CBD_SBSTTA_synbio.pdf.

  20. 20.

    As Peter Dabrock rightly observes (2009, 47): ““Playing God”—this reproach has accompanied modern biotechnology from its very beginnings. Almost every step forward in research has provoked vehement protest against the disregarding of creation: anaesthesia against pain, the birth control pill, transplantation medicine and diagnosing brain death, stem cell research and genetic engineering and many more innovations were faced with this reproach” For this history, Dabrock refers to Ramsey (1970), Chadwick (1989) and Coady (2009).

  21. 21.

    Mary Shelley portrays Victor Frankenstein as running away from his own creation, unable to interact with it. Thus the tragic life of a lonely and rejected new creature begins.

  22. 22.

    Church and Regis (2012), 137–140.

  23. 23.

    A difference remains: the hubris-interpretation links the dangerous outcomes to a certain attitude of the agent while the Sorcerer's Apprentice-version is focusing primarily on the uncontrollable outcomes, independently from the dubious character of their creator.

  24. 24.

    This influence has also been considered in the context of applied ethics, for example in healthcare. As Judith A. Erlen observes (1994, 66): “The promise of technology has the potential to act as a seductive force luring nurses and other health care providers to use it and luring patients to request it.”.

  25. 25.

    Cohen, Patricia (Jan 31, 2008). “Economists Dissect the ‘Yuck’ Factor”. The New York Times. See also Fukayama and McGibben.

  26. 26.

    Utilitarianism (an ethical theory of balancing pains and happiness or human preferences) has traditionally not offered any such boundary and was much criticised for the consequent problems. As a result, modern versions of Utilitarianism tend to include human freedom (and basic human rights) as such a boundary, thereby making the theory internally less consistent but its moral judgements more plausible.

  27. 27.

    Cf. for example G. Church (http://www.spiegel.de/international/zeitgeist/george-church-explains-how-dna-will-be-construction-material-of-the-future-a-877634-2.html; 12.7.2013).

  28. 28.

    Philippa Foot’s argument in Natural Goodness (2001) does not help. She claims that each species has its own standard as to how it should be treated, namely, in such a way that members of the species may realize their potential. This argument cannot say anything about the morality of the creation of new species.

  29. 29.

    Which he defines rather intuitively as “a situation in which the decision maker lacks much of the information that is taken for granted in the textbook cases” (1996, p. 369).

  30. 30.

    Biodiversity loss is a pivotal driver of ecosystem change (cf. Hooper et al. 2012).

  31. 31.

    Cf. http://www.cbd.int/cop9/doc/ (1.1.2014).

  32. 32.

    From Hasting’s Center press information (September 11, 2008); cf. September 12 Issue of Science.

  33. 33.

    See Sect. 6.4. in this book.

  34. 34.

    Ibid.

  35. 35.

    Some argue for an even more limited role of ethics, namely that it should confine itself to mediating between different positions and interests.

  36. 36.

    For this see also the 2010 report of the Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethics.

  37. 37.

    One has the impression that some are hostile to any ethics, seeing ethics as a threat to science, as a set of obstructive restrictions from an ill-informed public or religious grouping. If such scientists can see any purpose in public debate, then it is as a means of creating a climate of confidence and to secure public funding for further research. Admittedly, this picture is a bit of a caricature. But the reality is sometimes not very sophisticated.

  38. 38.

    Replacement happens on two levels: a better-adapted strain of one species replaces other strains of that same species, and successful species can replace other species. In the case of biotic artefacts, the first is less dangerous than the second, but even the first is potentially harmful: it means that the new life form may become better and better adapted to its environment and therefore more and amore able to interact with it.

References

  • Aus der Au C (2008) Der Begriff der Natur in der Debatte über die grüne Gentechnik. In: Busch RJ, Pütz G (eds) Biotechnologie in gesellschaftlicher Deutung, Utz, München, pp 21–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon F (1711) Meditationes Sacrae 1597. In: The works, with several additional pieces never before printed in any edition of his works. to which is prefixed a new life of the author by Mr. Mallet, vol II, London, pp 402–403

    Google Scholar 

  • Balmer A, Martin P (2008) Synthetic biology. Social and ethical challenges. An independent review commissioned by the Biotechnology and Biological Sciences Research Council (BBSRC). http://www.bbsrc.ac.uk/organisation/policies/reviews/scientific-areas/0806-synthetic-biology.aspx. Accessed 2 July 2013

  • Bedau MA et al (2009) Social and ethical checkpoints for bottom-up synthetic biology, or protocells. Syst Synth Biol 3:65–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett G, Gilman N (2009) From synthetic biology to biohacking: are we prepared? Nat Biotechnol 27(12):1109–1111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block WE (2012) Synthetic biology does not need a synthetic bioethics: give me that old time (Libertarian) ethics. Ethics Policy Environ 15(1) (available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2032738)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bodnar I (2012) Aristotle’s natural philosophy the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2012 Edition) (http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/aristotle-natphil/)

  • Boldt J, Müller O (2008) Newtons of the leaves of grass. Nat Biotechnol 26(4):387–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boldt J, Müller O, Maio G (2009) Synthetische Biologie. Eine ethisch-philosophische Analyse. BBL, Bern

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown D (2012) Navigating the perfect moral storm: climate ethics. Earthscan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bugl H et al (2007) DNA synthesis and biological security. Nat Biotechnol 25(6):627–629

    Google Scholar 

  • Burckhardt K (1878) Die Cultur der Renaissance in Italien, Basel

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplan A (2010) The end of vitalism. Nature 465:423

    Google Scholar 

  • Chadwick R (1989) Playing God. Cogito 3:186–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cho MK, Magnus D et al (1999) Genetics: ethical considerations in synthesizing a minimal genome. Science 286(5447):2087–2090

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Church G, Regis E (2012) Regenesis. How synthetic biology will reinvent nature and ourselves. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Coady CAJ (2009) Playing God. In: Savulescu J, Bostrom N (eds) Human enhancement. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 155–180

    Google Scholar 

  • Cockell CS (2005) The value of microorganisms. Environ Ethics 27(4):375–390

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Connor MR, Atsumi S (2010) Synthetic biology guides biofuel production (review article). J Biomed Biotechnol 2010. CSO SynBio submission to CBD SBSTTA Oct 2011. (http://www.econexus.info/publication/potential-impacts-synthetic-biology-biodiversity). Accessed 13 Dec 2013

    Google Scholar 

  • Dabrock P (2009) Playing God? Synthetic biology as a theological and ethical challenge. Syst Synth Biol 3(1–4):47–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1993) The autobiography of Charles Darwin (Barlow N ed). W.W. Norton Co, United States

    Google Scholar 

  • DeMarco D (1986) The dispute between Galileo and the Catholic Church. Homilet Pastor Rev CI 3(23–51):53–59

    Google Scholar 

  • Deplazes A, Huppenbauer M (2009) Synthetic organisms and living machines: positioning the products of synthetic biology at the borderline between living and non-living matter. Syst Synth Biol 3(1–4):55–63

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupuy J-P (2009) Technology and Metaphysics. In: Olsen JKB, Pedersen SA, Hendricks VF (eds) A companion to the philosophy of technology. Blackwell, New York, pp 214–217

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (2000) Sovereign virtue. The theory and practice of equality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Eason RE (2012) Synthetic biology already has a model to follow. Ethics Policy Environ 15(1):21–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ekeli KS (2004) Environmental risks, uncertainty and intergenerational ethics. Environ Values 13:421–448

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erlen J (1994) Technology’s seductive power. Orthop Nurs 13(6):5–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ETC Group (2007) Extreme genetic engineering. An introduction to synthetic biology. http://www.etcgroup.org/content/extreme-genetic-engineering-introduction-synthetic-biology. Accessed 27 April 2013

  • Foot P (2001) Natural goodness. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friends of the Earth (2012) Annual report. http://www.foei.org/wp-content/uploads/2013/12/Annual-report-2012.pdf

  • Funtowicz SO, Ravetz JR (1990) The emergence of post-normal science. In: von Schomberg R (ed) Science, politics, and morality: scientific uncertainty and decision making. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 85–123

    Google Scholar 

  • Galilei G (1842) Opere Complete di Galileo Galilei, Florence

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaskell G et al (2010) Europeans and biotechnology in 2010. Winds of change? European Commission

    Google Scholar 

  • Grunwald A (2009) Technology assessment: concepts and methods. In: Dov M, Meijers A, Woods J (eds) Handbook of the philosophy of science. Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences, vol 9. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 1103–1146

    Google Scholar 

  • Haker H (2012) Eine Verhältnisbestimmung von Theologie und Synthetischer Biologie aus ethischer Sicht. In: Köchy K, Hümpel A (eds) Synthetische Biologie. Entwicklung einer neuen Ingenieursbiologie? Themenband der interdisziplinären Arbeitsgruppe Gentechnologiebericht. Forum W, Dornburg, pp 195–213

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson SO (1996) Decision making under great uncertainty. Philos Soc Sci 26:369–386

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson SO (2009) Technology, prosperity, and risk. In: Olsen JKB, Pedersen SA, Hendricks VF (eds) A companion to the philosophy of technology. Blackwell, New York, pp 484–494

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauskeller M (2006) Verantwortung für das Leben? Schweitzers Dilemma. In: Hauskeller M (ed) Ethik des Lebens. Graue Edition, Zug, pp 210–236

    Google Scholar 

  • Heaf D, Wirz J (eds) (2002) Genetic engineering and the intrinsic value and integrity of plants and animals, work-shop, royal botanic garden. Edinburgh. Ifgene, Dornach, pp 5–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Heavey P (2013) The place of God in synthetic biology: how will the Catholic Church respond? Bioethics 27(1):36–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (2002) Die Technik und die Kehre. Cotta, Stuttgart

    Google Scholar 

  • Hösle V (1991) Philosophie der ökologischen Krise: Moskauer Vorträge. Beck, München

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooper D et al (2012) A global synthesis reveals biodiversity loss as a major driver of ecosystem change. Nature 486:105–108

    Google Scholar 

  • Hümpel A,Diekämper J (2012) Daten zu ausgewählten Indikatoren. In: Köchy K, Hümpel A (eds) Synthetische Biologie. Entwicklung einer neuen Ingenieursbiologie? Themenband der interdisziplinären Arbeitsgruppe Gentechnologiebericht. Forum W, Dornburg, pp 264–265

    Google Scholar 

  • Illies C (2006a) Philosophische Anthropologie im biologischen Zeitalter. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M

    Google Scholar 

  • Illies C (2006b) Ehrfurcht statt Begründung? Albert Schweitzers Versuch einer Grundlegung der Ethik. In: Hauskeller M (ed) Ethik des Lebens, Graue Edition, Zug, pp. 189–209

    Google Scholar 

  • Illies C, Meijers A (2009) Artefacts without agency. Monist 92(3):422–443

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas H (1984) The imperative of responsibility. UCP, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas H (1987) Technik, Medizin und Ethik. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan A, O’Riordan T (2004) The precautionary principle: a legal and policy history. In: Martuzzi M, Tickner JA (eds) The precautionary principle: protecting public health, the environment and the future of our children. World Health Organization (1), pp 31–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaebnick GE (2009) Synthetic biology: engineering life. Lahey Clin J Med Ethics 16(3):6–7

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1790) Kritik der Urteilskraft. Akademie Ausgabe Vol. 5. De Gruyter, Berlin 1968

    Google Scholar 

  • Kass L (1997) The wisdom of repugnance. The New Republic (2 June 1997), pp 17–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight FH (1921) Risk, uncertainty and profit. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee K (2009) Biology and Technology. In: Olsen JKB, Pedersen SA, Hendricks VF (eds) A companion to the philosophy of technology. Blackwell, New York, pp 99–103

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lockhart T (2000) Moral uncertainty and its consequences. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwith K (1986) Vicos Grundsatz: verum et factum convertuntur. Seine theologische Prämisse und deren säkulare Konsequenzen. In: Sämtliche Schriften, Band 9. Metzler, Stuttgart, pp 195–227

    Google Scholar 

  • Marliere P (2009) The farther, the safer: a manifesto for securely navigating synthetic species away from the old living world. Syst Synth Biol 3(1–4):77–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mazis GA (2008) Animals, humans, machines. Blurring boundaries. Suny Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitcham C, Waelbers K (2009) Technology and ethics: overview. In: Olsen JKB, Pedersen SA, Hendricks VF (eds) A companion to the philosophy of technology. Blackwell, New York, pp 367–383

    Google Scholar 

  • Monoid J (1970) Le hasard et la nécessité. Essai sur la philosophie naturelle de la biologie modern. Le Seuil, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore D, Loewenstein G (2004) Self-interest, automaticity, and the psychology of conflict of interest. Soc Justice Res 17(2):189–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller A (2004) Lasst uns Menschen machen!. Kohlhammer, Stuttgart

    Google Scholar 

  • Na J (2002) Praktische vernunft und geschichte bei vico und hegel. Königshausen und Neumann, Würzburg  

    Google Scholar 

  • Parens E, Johnston J et al (2008) Ethics: do we need “synthetic bioethics”? Science 321(5895):1449

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preston C (2008) Synthetic biology: drawing a line in Darwin’s sand. Environ Values 17(1):23–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey P (1970) Fabricated man. The ethics of genetic control. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1971) Theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt M (2008) Diffusion of synthetic biology: a challenge to biosafety. Syst Synth Biol 2(1–2):1–6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt M (2010) Xenobiology: a new form of life as the ultimate biosafety tool. BioEssays 32(4):322–331

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schweitzer A (2003) Die Ehrfurcht vor dem Leben. Beck, München

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmel G (1900) Philosophie des Geldes. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt a. M. 1994

    Google Scholar 

  • Tannert C, Elvers H-D, Jamdrig B (2007) The ethics of uncertainty. EMBO Rep 8(10):892–896

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tait J (2009) Upstream engagement and the governance of science. The shadow of the genetically modified crops experience in Europe. EMBO reports 10, S18–S22

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson P (2012) Synthetic biology needs a synthetic bioethics. Ethics Policy Environ 15(1):1–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Torgersen H (2009) Synthetic biology in society: learning from past experience? Syst Synth Biol 3(1–4):9–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Tumpey et al (2005) Characterization of the reconstructed 1918 Spanish influenza Pandemic Virus. Science 310 (5745):77–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Asselt M, Vos E (2006) The precautionary principle and the uncertainty paradox. J Risk Res 9(4):313–336

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Den Belt H (2009) Playing God in Frankenstein’s footsteps: synthetic biology and the meaning of life. Nanoethics 3(3):257–268

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek P-P (2005) What things do. Philosophical reflections on technology, agency, and design. Pennsylvania State University Press, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • Vico G (1710) De antiquissima Italorum sapientia, ex linguae latinae originibus eruenda. Nabu Press 2011

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (1934) Die protestantische Ethik und der Geist des Kapitalismus. Mohr, Tübingen

    Google Scholar 

  • White L Jr (1978) Medieval religion and technology: collected essays. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • White EB (2007) Letters of E.B. White. Harper Perennial; Reprint edition

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1985) Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Collins, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Winner L (1980) Do artefacts have politics? Daedalus 109(1):121–136

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Illies .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Illies, C. (2016). New Debates in Old Ethical Skins. In: Engelhard, M. (eds) Synthetic Biology Analysed. Ethics of Science and Technology Assessment, vol 44. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-25145-5_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-25145-5_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-25143-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-25145-5

  • eBook Packages: EngineeringEngineering (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics