Skip to main content

Cognition as Higher-Order Regulation

  • Chapter
Computing and Philosophy

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 375))

Abstract

The chapter discusses Antonio Damasio’s understanding of higher-level neurological and psychological functions in Self Comes to Mind (2010) and argues that the distinction he posits between regulatory (homeostatic) physiological structures and non-regulatory higher-level structures such as drives, motivations (and, ultimately, consciousness) presents philosophical and technical problems. The paper suggests that a purely regulatory understanding of drives and motivations (and, consequently, of cognition as well) as higher-order regulations could provide a unified theoretical framework capable of overcoming the old split between cognition and homeostasis that keeps resurfacing, under different guises, in the technical as well as in the non-technical understandings of consciousness and associated concepts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In the De natura deorum, for instance, Cicero says of the gods that “they raised men from the ground and made them stand erect so that by looking at the heavens they could get knowledge of the gods” (Qui primum eos humo excitatos celsos et erectos constituit, ut deorum cognitionem caelum intuentes capere possent)” (d.N.D, II, 140, 1933, 56). A similar use of cognitio is in the De officiis (I,43), where Cicero speaks of the “knowledge and contemplation of nature (cognitio contemplatioque naturae)” (1938, 153). The term is very frequent in his works and can be found also in the Tusculan Disputations, the De finibus, etc. The nominal use of the term is standard in the technical Latin of Medieval and Modern philosophy, as attested, for instance, by Aquinas, Spinoza, and Descartes.

  2. 2.

    This is the basis of Aristotle’s definition, for instance, and it is accepted wholeheartedly by the Medieval tradition that refers to him, with the slight modifications necessary to make it fit the Christian view of humans created in God’s image. Early Modern Western philosophy follows in the same vein.

  3. 3.

    1976, 1, my emph. Indeed, contemporary studies in animal cognition adapt Neisser’s definition while inserting an explicit reference to animals in general. See, for instance, Sarah Shettleworth: “Cognition refers to the mechanisms by which animals acquire, process, store, and act on information from the environment. These include perception, learning, memory, and decision-making. The study of comparative cognition is therefore concerned with how animals process information, starting with how information is acquired by the senses” (2009, 4).

  4. 4.

    As Aristotle argues in Eth. Nic. I,7, 1098b1-18.

  5. 5.

    See Eth Nic. X, 6–9, as well as the similar Platonic theory of intellectual pleasure that Socrates develops in Rep. IX, 585b and ff.

  6. 6.

    This use of “dynamic” as a short-hand for a causal explanation of behavior will probably sound rather strange to 21st scientists. As Gordana Dodig Crnkovic noted (personal communication), a physicist, when seeing the word “dynamic” in a scientific context such as Neisser’s, will most likely think of dynamic attractors that lie below cognitive processes and which stand for particular mechanisms and not for motives. In other words, when a physicist points us toward a “dynamic explanation,” she is telling us that we should be looking for a particular class of mechanisms—namely, those governed by dynamic attractors—and not be on the lookout for a further causal level. As I explain below, Neisser’s now outdated usage of the term presupposes psychoanalysis’s own self-description and the contemporary (ultimately, nineteenth century) sub-divisions of classical mechanics.

  7. 7.

    See Franchi (2011b) for a detailed discussion of homeostasis, whose details and fascinating history I am forced to skip over in the present context.

  8. 8.

    See, for instance, the sweeping declaration on the need to ground “pain, pleasure, emotions, and feelings; social behaviors; religions; economies and their markets and financial institutions; moral behaviors; laws and justice; politics; art, technology, and science” in “life regulation” (2010, 63–64).

  9. 9.

    See Aristotle 1984, v. 2, 1734–1735=1097b–1098aand Franchi (2014).

  10. 10.

    (Freud 1953b,c). See Franchi (2011a) for a brief discussion of Freud’s and Lacan’s theory of the drive from an Ashby-inspired regulation perspective.

  11. 11.

    See the papers collected in Ashby (1981).

  12. 12.

    See Franchi (2011b) for and extended discussion of the incompatibility between the contemporary and Ashby’s approach to homeostasis and Franchi (2013) for a few, preliminary result on robotics simulations of a fully homeostatic Ashbian model of behavior.

  13. 13.

    The theory is sketched out in chapters 1517 of Design for a Brain. Empirical results about the necessary loose coupling of homeostatic sub-networks confirming the earlier theoretical analysis are provided in Ashby (1981).

  14. 14.

    See Pickering (2010) and Husbands and Holland (2008) for a discussion of Dams.

References

  • Aristotle. (1984). The complete works of Aristotle. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashby, W. R. (1960). Design for a brain (2nd ed.). London: Chapman and Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashby, W. R. (1981). Mechanisms of intelligence: Ross Ashby’s writings on cybernetics. Seaside: Intersystems Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cannon, W. (1939[1932]). The wisdom of the body (2nd ed.). New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero, M. T. (1933). De natura deorum (Loeb classical library). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero, M. T. (1938). De officiis (Loeb classical library). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (2010). Self comes to mind: Constructing the conscious brain. New York: Knopf Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Der, R. (2001). Self-organized acquisition of situated behaviors. Theory in Biosciences, 120(3), 179–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2000). Homeostatic adaptation to inversion of the visual field and other sensorimotor disruptions. In J. A. Meyer, A. Berthoz, D. Floreano, H. L. Roitblat, & S. W. Wilson (Eds.), From Animals to Animats 6: Proceedings of the 6th International Conference on the Simulation of Adaptive Behavior (pp. 440–449). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franchi, S. (2011a). Jammed machines and contingently fit animals: Psychoanalysis’s biological paradox. French Literature Studies, 38, 231–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franchi, S. (2011b). Life, death, and resurrection of the homeostat. In S. Franchi & F. Bianchini (Eds.), The search for a theory of cognition: Early mechanisms and new ideas (pp. 3–52). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Franchi, S. (2013). Homeostats for the 21st century? Lessons learned from simulating Ashby simulating the brain. Constructivist Foundations, 8(3), 501–532. With open peer commentaries and author’s response.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franchi, S. (2014). General homeostasis, autonomy, and heteroomy: Toward an affect-based theory of cognition. In V. Müller (Ed.), Fundamental Issues of Artificial Intelligence. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1953a). Standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud. London: Hogarth Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1953b). The standard edition of the psychological works of Sigmund Freud (chap Instincts and their vicissitudes, pp. 117–140). Vol 14 of Freud (1953a), written in 1915.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1953c). The standard edition of the psychological works of Sigmund Freud (chap. Project for a scientific psychology, pp 283–387). Vol 1 of Freud (1953a), written in 1895.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J. S. (1917). Organism and environment as illustrated by the physiology of breathing. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J. S. (1922). Respiration. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann, J. M., Holicki, M., & Der, R. (2004). On Ashby’s homeostat: A formal model of adaptive regulation. In S. Schaal (Ed.), From Animals to Animats 8. Proceedings of the Eighth International Conference on Simulation of Adaptive Behavior (pp. 324–333). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, C. L. (1943). Principles of behavior. An introduction to behavior theory. New York: D. Appleton-Century.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husbands, P., & Holland, O. (2008). The Ratio Club: A hub of British cybernetics. In P. Husbands, O. Holland, & M. Wheeler (Eds.), The mechanical mind in history (pp. 91–148). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Iizuka, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2007). Toward spinozist robotics: Exploring the minimal dynamics of behavioral preference. Adaptive Behavior, 15(4), 359–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ikegami, T., & Suzuki, K. (2008). From a homeostatic to a homeodynamic self. Biosystems, 91(2), 388–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life: Towards a philosophical biology. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1984). The imperative of responsibility. Foundations of an ethics for the technological age. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. (1967). Cognitive psychology. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. (1976). Cognition and reality. Principles and implications of cognitive psychology. New York: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1967). Biologie et connaissance. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2004). Functionalism, computationalism, and mental states. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 35, 811–833.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (2010). The cybernetic brain: Sketches of another future. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shettleworth, S. J. (2009). Cognition, evolution, and behavior. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, H. (2006). Homeostatic adaptive networks. PhD thesis, University of Leeds

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, H., & Noble, J. (2007). Homeostatic plasticity improves signal propagation in continuous-time recurrent neural networks. Biosystems, 87(2–3), 252–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stefano Franchi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Franchi, S. (2016). Cognition as Higher-Order Regulation. In: Müller, V.C. (eds) Computing and Philosophy. Synthese Library, vol 375. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-23291-1_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics