Skip to main content

Majority Decision

  • Chapter
  • 446 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in Choice and Welfare ((WELFARE))

Abstract

This chapter provides a brief history of voting and of collective decision-making, especially in the medieval Catholic Church and in the late medieval and early modern representative bodies. The focal questions are how and why people accepted the authority of any purely mechanical procedure—be it the simple majority-principle, a two-third rule, or something else. This is not just a historical problem. Rather, some important theoretical disputes on the nature of democracy are related to this issue. The development of democracy can been as a breakthrough of the legitimacy of purely mechanical procedures. I present the most elementary result of the social-choice theory: the so-called May’s Theorem. I review the discussions about the theorem and try to show how, contrary to some claims, it captures at least a part of the democratic idea of political equality. The “paradoxes” of the social choice emerge when we move away from the simplest case characterized by a single issue, only two options, and a direct choice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On the history of the majority principle in general, see: Baty (1912); Heinberg (1926); Heun (1983); Konopczynski (1930); Moulin (1953).

  2. 2.

    For an opposite view, see Lijphart (1991) and Hyland (1995).

  3. 3.

    In an interesting article Hastie and Kameda (2005) argue that the majority rule is psychologically salient as well as practically effective. They claim that the rule is popular “across the full spectrum of human groups from hunter-gatherer tribal societies to modern industrial democracies” (pp. 494, 495). However, the sources mentioned by them do not actually give much support to the claim that the rule has been popular among hunter-gatherers, although they present some real evidence that many non-human animals living in packs do follow “majorities”.

  4. 4.

    Philippe Urfalino (2006, 2007) has remarked that the version of unanimity used in many non-European and pre-modern European assemblies should be characterized as the rule of apparent consensus rather than that of formal unanimity. Under apparent consensus, there is no separate stage of voting and no formal veto-rights. Instead, issues are discussed and negotiated, and the process continues until there is no open disagreement. There is no well-defined default rule: if an agreement cannot be reached, decisions are postponed or transferred to another body. Sometimes, stubborn minorities are simply excluded from further discussions or forced to submit by informal coercion. Such a rule should be distinguished from the formal veto—rule used in international congresses of the States or in the seventeenth and eighteenth century Polish sejm.

  5. 5.

    Moulin ascribes this phrase first (Moulin, 1953, 127) to Gregory X and then (Moulin, 1958, 514) to Boniface VIII.

  6. 6.

    This did make the process smoother but not necessarily less complicated. For example, in 1740, Pope Benedict XIV was elected in the 225th ballot. John Paul II was the next pope who changed the rules: he ordered that, after 33 unsuccessful ballots, a simple majority was sufficient for election. However, in 2007, Benedict XVI reversed the amendment and restored the old two-thirds rule.

  7. 7.

    This complaint was common in those days. For example, when Andrew Melville, the Scottish reformer, refused to acknowledge a decision made in the presbytery of St. Andrews in 1591, he stated “quod suffragia essent ponderanda, non numeranda” (that votes should be weighed, not counted) (MacDonald, 2010).

  8. 8.

    On Plato’s argument, see Crito 47c–d2, Gorgias 463d1–465e1, Republic I 341c4–342e11.

  9. 9.

    See also Dahl (1989, 63–64).

  10. 10.

    Thus, J. S. Mill’s famous plural-vote scheme (Mill, 1861/1972, 283–290) can be seen as an attempt to balance his radical proposal of general suffrage with a relatively familiar and widely accepted conservative element. After a consideration, Mill rejects another common device, the use of indirect elections (pp. 293–298).

  11. 11.

    One of the institutions that the Bolsheviks adopted from the Czarist government was the totally arbitrary division of electoral constituencies and the attached system of indirect elections; both were in use in the first elections of the national Soviets.

  12. 12.

    The two-thirds—rule was introduced by the Southern Democrats in 1844. At the 1860 convention, it caused a split in the party. No candidate could win the required super-majority, so the northerners nominated Douglas and the southerners nominated Breckinridge.

  13. 13.

    A similar deadlock appeared in the Moldovan presidential elections 2009–2010. The Moldovan parliament chose the President with a 3/5-majority. After two subsequent failed elections, the parliament had to be dissolved. Neither the Communists (the largest party) nor their opponents were able to find the required supermajority. First the opposition forced new parliamentary elections by deadlocking the presidential elections; after losing their parliamentary majority, the Communists adopted a similar strategy.

  14. 14.

    The problems related to “the act of not choosing” have been neglected in the formal theories of choice. There is a brief comment on the issue in Frohlich and Oppenheimer (1978), pp. 9–10. On “non-decisions” in political theory, see the classical article of Bachrach and Baratz (1963).

  15. 15.

    Here the problem of tied results is abstracted away. When the number of voters is even, the absolute-majority rule may produce ties. If there is no tie-breaking rule, and both candidates cannot be elected simultaneously, the rule is not decisive. For this reason, most committees use some tie-breaking rule. If the chair has the power to break ties, anonymity is violated. If ties are broken by drawing lots, strong neutrality is violated. If the status quo wins in tied cases, weak neutrality is violated. All tie-breaking rules violate some of May’s conditions. So, some condition has to be sacrificed for decisiveness. This, I think, shows that a violation of a condition may sometimes be quite harmless. Still, people are not indifferent with respect to the alternative tie-breaking rules. For example, in European parliaments, ties on ordinary motions are usually solved by the status quo rule, while in electing the presiding officer ties are most often solved by drawing lots (Rasch, 1995, 500).

  16. 16.

    Switzerland is the crown jewel of the consociational theory of democracy. Since 1959, the posts in the federal government have been divided between the four main parties according to the “magic formula”. The election results have no effect on the composition of the government. If this were the full truth about the Swiss political system, the country could hardly be called a democracy. However, this consociational arrangement is balanced by the extensive use of the purely majoritarian referendum device.

  17. 17.

    Another context in which super-majority requirements are often applied is the regulation of relationships between separate democratically elected bodies. For example, overriding the veto of a second chamber or impeaching a democratically-elected President usually requires extraordinary majorities. In such situations, there is a majority-will operating against another majority-will, and it is a natural requirement to devise special qualifications in order to resolve the dispute. Schwartzberg (2014) argues that if it is necessary to violate neutrality in order to protect a minority, it is more advisable to violate anonymity too, by giving the protected minority an exclusive veto-right rather than establishing a general veto-right for all coalitions of a certain size.

  18. 18.

    On the “spurious” majorities in real-life elections, see Katz (2001) and Siaroff (2003).

  19. 19.

    Typically, these countries are (small) former British colonies.

  20. 20.

    In the Australian and Swiss federations, this principle governs the use of nation-wide constitutional referenda. In order to become a law, a proposal has to win a nation-wide majority of votes as well as a majority in a majority of the separate states or cantons. Because of the second requirement, a minority can prevent a proposal. If the sub-units are of different sizes, this minority may be very small. In Switzerland, the theoretical minimum is 9 % of those who vote (a 51 % majority in the smallest cantons).

  21. 21.

    Quorum requirements are sometimes applied in referenda. In the German States and in Hungary, a proposition is accepted only if at least 25 % of the eligible voters vote for a proposition; in Denmark 3/10 of voters have to support the proposition (2/5 in constitutional issues;, in Belarus, the support of a majority of all eligible voters is required. In Italy, Portugal, Romania, Moldova, Slovenia and Slovakia, more than a half of the electorate has to participate. Some countries define a quorum even for general elections (for example Thailand, Serbia, Russia, and Ukraine). If the voting turnout is not the required (usually, 50 % of the eligible voters) the proposition is rejected, or, in general elections, a new election has to be arranged. There is relatively little theoretical discussion on quorum requirements (see, however, Vermeule, 2007 and Laruelle & Valenciano, 2011), although they may have significant effects on decisions.

References

  • Ackerman, B. (1980). Social justice in the liberal state. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anckar, D. (2004). Författningsändring och problemlösning: En studie av kvalifierade majoriteter i 34 stater. Politiikka, 46, 239–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. N., & Anderson, P. R. (1967). Political institutions and social change in Continental Europe in the nineteenth century. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bachrach, P., & Baratz, M. S. (1963). Decisions and nondecisions. An analytical framework. American Political Science Review, 57, 641–651.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bagehot, W. (1867/2003). The English constitution. London: Fontana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbalet, J. M. (1988). Citizenship. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bardach, J. (1985). L’élection des députés à l’ancienne Diète polonais, fin XVe–XVIIIe siècles. Parliaments, Estates and Representation, 5, 45–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baty, T. P. (1912). The history of majority rule. The Quarterly Review, 201, 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beitz, C. (1989). Political equality: An essay in democratic theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams, S. J., & Fishburn, P. C. (2002). Voting procedures. In K. J. Arrow, A. K. Sen, & K. Suzumura (Eds.), Handbook of social choice and welfare (pp. 173–236). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brotherus, K. R. (1948). Katsaus Suomen valtiollisen järjestysmuodon kehitykseen (2nd ed.). Porvoo: WSOY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns, J. H. (2003). Majorities: An exploration. History of Political Thought, 24, 66–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calhoun, J. C. (1853/1953). A disquisition of government. New York: Liberal Arts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, C. P. (2006). Consistent representative democracy. Games and Economic Behaviour, 62, 348–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, T. (1990). Political equality. In J. W. Chapman & A. Wertheimer (Eds.), Majorities and minorities. Nomos XXXII (pp. 151–183). New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J. (1989). Rationality and the justification of democracy. In G. Brennan & L. Lomasky (Eds.), Politics and process (pp. 194–220). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J., & Ferejohn, J. (1986). Democracy and social choice. Ethics, 97, 6–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colomer, J. M. (2001). Political institutions: Democracy and social choice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Colomer, J., & McLean, I. (1998). Electing Popes: Approval balloting and qualified-majority rule. Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 29, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, R. A. (1989). Democracy and its critics. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1997). The principles of electoral reform. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, D. (2008). Democratic authority. A philosophical framework. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fanning, W. H. (1911). Papal election. In C. G. Hebermann et al. (Eds.), The Catholic encyclopedia (Vol. XI). New York: Robert Appleton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forsyth, M. (1981). Unions of states. The theory and practice of confederation. New York: Leicester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frohlich, N., & Oppenheimer, J. A. (1978). Modern political economy. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (1991). Public justification and democratic adjudication. Constitutional Political Economy, 2, 251–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gil, X. (1993). Crown and Córtes in early modern Aragon: Reassessing revisionisms. Parliaments, Estates and Representation, 13, 109–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. E., & List, C. (2006). Special majorities rationalized. British Journal of Political Science, 36, 213–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, K. (1982). Democracy and the autonomous moral agent. In K. Graham (Ed.), Contemporary political philosophy. Radical studies (pp. 113–137). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grotius, H. (1625/1853). The rights of peace and war (W. Whewell, Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gueneé, B. (1985). States and rulers in later medieval Europe (J. Vale, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hastie, R., & Kameda, T. (2005). The robust beauty of majority rules in group decisions. Psychological Review, 112, 494–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heinberg, J. G. (1926). History of the majority principle. American Political Science Review, 20, 52–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herde, P. (1985). Election and abdication of the Pope: Practice and doctrine in the thirteenth century. In Proceedings of the sixth international congress of medieval canon law. Monumenta Iuris Canoninci. Series C subsidia 7 (pp. 411–436). Citta del Vaticano: Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heun, W. (1983). Das Mehrheitsprinzip in der Demokratie. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, D. (1975). The representative of the people? Voters and voting in England under the early Stuarts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Holden, A. M. (1930). The imperative mandate in the Spanish Cortes of the middle ages. American Political Science Review, 24, 886–912.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hyland, J. L. (1995). Democratic theory. The philosophical foundations. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jefferson, T. (1784/1944). Notes on the state of Virginia. In A. Koch & W. Peden (Eds.), The life and selected writings of Thomas Jefferson (pp. 187–288). New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, P. (1988). Intense preferences, strong beliefs and democratic decision-making. Political Studies, 36, 7–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katz, R. S. (2001). The 2000 presidential election: A perverse outcome? Representation, 38, 141–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, H. (1945). The general theory of law and state (A. Wedberg, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kishlansky, M. A. (1986). Parliamentary selection: Social and political choice in early modern England. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Konopczynski, L. (1930). Le liberum veto. Étude sur le dévélopment du principe majoritaire. Paris: Champion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krabbe, H. (1930). The modern idea of the state (G. H. Sabine, Trans.). New York: Appleton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laruelle, A., & Valenciano, F. (2011). Majorities with a quorum. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 23, 241–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, A. (1981). Liberal democracy: A critique of its theory. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewin, L. (1988). Utilitarianism and rational choice. European Journal of Political Research, 16, 29–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lijphart, A. (1984). Democracies: Patterns of majoritarian and consensus government in twenty-one countries. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lijphart, A. (1991). Majority rule in theory and practice: The tenacity of a flawed paradigm. International Social Science Journal, 129, 483–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacDonald, A. (2010). Voting in the Scottish parliament before 1639. Parliaments, Estates, and Representation, 30, 145–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacPherson, C. B. (1977). The life and times of liberal democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Małłek, J. (2005). The estate system of politics and political culture in the two parts of Prussia (Royal Prussia and the Duchy of Prussia) in early modern times. Parliaments, Estates and Representation, 25, 11–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäntylä, I. (1977). Yksimielisyydestä kauppiaiden valtaan. Raatimiesten vaalit 12 kaupungissa 1722-1808. Historiallisia tutkimuksia 104. Helsinki: Suomen historiallinen seura.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäntylä, I. (1981). Valitut, ehdollepannut ja nimitetyt. Pormestarin vaalit 20 kaupungissa 1720-1808. Historiallisia tutkimuksia 114. Helsinki: Suomen historiallinen seura.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marongiu, A. (1949/1968). Medieval parliaments. A comparative study (S. J. Woolf, Trans.). London: Eyre & Spottiswoode.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1871/1958). The civil war in France. In K. Marx & F. Engels, Selected works. Moscow: Progress.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matinolli, E. (1955). Turun hiippakunnan papinvaalit ja papinvirkojen täyttäminen aikakautena 1721-1808. Turku: Turun yliopiston julkaisuja B 51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matinolli, E. (1957). Porvoon hiippakunnan papinvaalit ja papinvirkojen täyttäminen aikakautena 1721-1808. Turku: Turun yliopiston julkaisuja B 66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellquist, E. D. (1974). Rösträtt efter förtjänst. Riksdagsdebatten om den kommunala rösträtten i Sverige 1866-1900. Stockholm: Stadshistoriska Institutet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1861/1972). Considerations on representative government. In H. B. Acton (Ed.) Utilitarianism, on liberty, and considerations on representative government. London: Dent.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monahan, A. P. (1987). Consent, coercion and limit. The medieval origins of parliamentary democracy. Kingston, NY: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, L. (1953). Les origines religieuses des techniques électorales et déliberatives modernes. Revue internationale d’histoire politique et constitutionelle, Nouvelle série, 3, 106–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, L. (1958). Sanior et maior pars. Note sur l’evolution des techniques électorales dans les Ordres religieux du VIe au XIIIe siècle. Revue historique de droit Français et étranger, 35, 368–397 & 491–529.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, L. (1965). Policy-making in the religious orders. Government and Opposition, 1, 25–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myers, A. R. (1975). Parliaments and estates in Europe to 1789. London: Thames & Hudson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, W. A. (1980). On justifying democracy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nermuth, M. (1992). Two-stage discrete aggregation: The Ostrogorski paradox and related phenomena. Social Choice and Welfare, 9, 99–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norman, R. (1987). Free and equal. A philosophical examination of political values. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (1987). Comparing voting systems. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (1988). On rationality and legitimacy of voting procedures. In D. Anckar et al. (Eds.), Rationality and legitimacy (pp. 129–145). Jyväskylä: Finnish Political Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (1998). Voting paradoxes and referenda. Social Choice and Welfare, 15, 333–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Offe, C. (1985). Disorganized capitalism. Oxford: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennington, K. (1995). Law, legislative authority, and theories of government: 1150-1300. In J. H. Burns (Ed.), The Cambridge history of medieval political thought (pp. 424–453). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pildes, R. H., & Anderson, E. S. (1990). Slinging arrows at democracy: Social choice theory, value pluralism, and democratic politics. Columbia Law Review, 90, 2121–2214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pufendorf, S. (1688/1934). De jure naturae et gentium libri octo (C. H. Oldfather & W. A. Oldfather, Trans.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasch, B. E. (1995). Parliamentary voting procedures. In H. Döring (Ed.), Parliaments and majority rule in Western Europe (pp. 488–527). Frankfurt: Campus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renvall, P. (1962). Suomen kansanedustuksen vaiheet 1850-luvun puoliväliin: Ruotsin vallan aika. In Suomen kansanedustuslaitoksen historia I (pp. 11–448). Helsinki: Eduskunnan historiakomitea.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1984). Electoral systems and constitutional restraints. In A. Lijphart & B. Grofman (Eds.), Choosing an electoral system. Issues and alternatives (pp. 103–110). New York: Prager.

    Google Scholar 

  • Risse, M. (2004). Arguing for majority rule. Journal of Political Philosophy, 12, 41–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, G. J. A. (Ed.). (1995). Leviathan contemporary responses to the political theory of Thomas Hobbes. Bristol: Thoemmes Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roháč, D. (2008). The unanimity rule and the religious fractionalisation in the Polish-Lithuanian Republic. Journal of Constitutional Political Economics, 19, 111–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadurski, W. (2008). Equality and legitimacy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, B. (2010). Democracy, political equality, and majority rule. Ethics, 121, 148–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saward, M. (1998). The terms of democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiller, W., & Stewart, C., III. (2004). U.S. Senate Elections before 1914. http://polisci.wisc.edu/-coleman/apd/schillerstewart.pdf

  • Schmitt, C. (1928/2008). Constitutional theory (J. Seitzer, Trans.). Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulze, W. (1986). Majority decision in the imperial diets of sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Journal of Modern History, 58(supplement), 46–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartzberg, M. (2014). Counting the many. The origins and limits of supermajoritarian rules. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siaroff, A. (2003). Spurious majorities, electoral systems, and electoral system change. Commonwealth & Comparative Politics, 41, 143–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spitz, E. (1984). Majority rule. Chatham, NJ: Chatham House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Théry, J. (2001). Moyen Âge. In P. Perrineau & D. Reynié (Eds.), Dictionnaire du vote (pp. 667–678). Paris: Presses universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tideman, N. (2006). Collective decisions and voting. The potential for public choice. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urfalino, P. (2006). Apparent consensus and voting: Two modes of collective decision-making. A paper presented at the workshop on the mechanisms of collective decision-making, Adriano Olivetti Foundation, Rome.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urfalino, P. (2007). L’esprit des regles de decision. In C. Michon & B. Gnassounou (Eds.), Vincent descombes. Questions disputées (pp. 199–235). Paris: Cécile Defaut.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urwin, D. W. (1974). Germany: Continuity and change in electoral politics. In R. Rose (Ed.), Electoral behaviour: A comparative handbook. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermeule, A. (2007). Mechanisms of democracy: Institutional design writ small. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (1999a). The dignity of legislation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (1999b). Law and disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice. A defence of pluralism and equality. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weale, A. (1999). Democracy. London: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1917/1994). Suffrage and democracy in Germany. In M. Weber (Ed.), Political writings (P. Lassman & R. Speirs Trans. & Ed., pp. 80–129). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. K. (2002). Transitional governance in the United States: Lessons from the First Federal Congress. In G. Loewenberg, P. Squire, & D. R. Kiewet (Eds.), Legislatures. Comparative perspectives on representative assemblies. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, R. P. (1970/1976). In defense of anarchism. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lagerspetz, E. (2016). Majority Decision. In: Social Choice and Democratic Values. Studies in Choice and Welfare. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-23261-4_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics