Skip to main content

Pragmatists and Purists on CPT Invariance in Relativistic Quantum Field Theories

  • Chapter
Recent Developments in the Philosophy of Science: EPSA13 Helsinki

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS,volume 1))

  • 806 Accesses

Abstract

An influential claim in the physics literature states that the violation of CPT invariance in an interacting RQFT entails the violation of Lorentz invariance. This claim is surprising since standard proofs of the CPT theorem require more assumptions than Lorentz invariance, and are restricted to non-interacting, or at best, unrealistic interacting theories. This essay analyzes this claim in the context of the debate between pragmatist approaches to RQFTs, which trade mathematical rigor for the ability to derive predictions from realistic interacting theories, and purist approaches, which trade the ability to formulate realistic interacting theories for mathematical rigor.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Another purist approach is the algebraic formalism which will not be discussed in this essay. CPT theorems have been proven in the algebraic approach by Borchers and Yngvason (2001) and Guido and Longo (1995). For a brief discussion of the latter, see Bain (2013).

  2. 2.

    A Jost point (x 1, …, x n ) is a convex set of points that are spacelike separated from each other. In other words, the difference variables \( {\xi}_i\equiv {x_i}_{-1} - {x}_i \) satisfy \( {\left(\sum {\lambda}_j{\xi}_j\right)}^2 < 0,\ \mathrm{f}\mathrm{o}\mathrm{r}{\lambda}_{\mathrm{j}}\ \ge\ 0,\sum {\lambda}_{\mathrm{j}} > 0 \) (Streater and Wightman 1964, p. 71).

  3. 3.

    This is reflected in Weinberg’s (1995, p. 198) view of the axiomatic assumption of local commutativity (i.e., fields at spacelike separated points commute): “The point taken here is that [local commutativity of fields] is needed for the Lorentz invariance of the S-matrix, without any ancillary assumptions about measurability or causality.”

  4. 4.

    In other words, a model of the Wightman axioms need not take the form of a Fock space representation of the canonical (anti-) commutation relations. Note that the basic objects of the Wightman approach are tempered distributions (i.e., Wightman functions), but Wightman’s (1956) reconstruction theorem indicates that these can be interpreted as vacuum expectation values of unordered products of fields.

  5. 5.

    Lévy-Leblond (1967, p. 165) explains the failure of the CPT theorem in GQFTs as due to the fact that GQFTs do not satisfy local commutativity: “This situation [i.e., the GQFT case] is to be contrasted with the relativistic case where the requirements of local commutativity on a free field… impose both the existence of a TCP [i.e., CPT] operation… and the spin-statistics relation, as has been shown in a very illuminating way, for this free-field case, by Weinberg…”

  6. 6.

    The Hamiltonian is related to the Hamiltonian density by \( H(t) = \int {d}^3\mathbf{x}\mathcal{H}\left(\mathbf{x},t\right) \).

  7. 7.

    ϕ I (x) is defined by \( {\phi}_I\left(\mathbf{x},t\right)\equiv {e}^{i{H_0}\left(t-t_0\right)}\phi \left(\mathbf{x},{t}_0\right){e}^{-i{H_0}\left(t-t_0\right)} \), where ϕ(x, t 0) is a non-interacting field at time t 0.

  8. 8.

    As Weinberg (1995, p. 441) states, “…the renormalization of masses and fields has nothing directly to do with the presence of infinities, and would be necessary even in a theory in which all momentum space integrals were convergent.”

  9. 9.

    An important exception to this is QCD, which is not weakly coupled.

  10. 10.

    Causal perturbation theory consists of both a regularization scheme to address UV divergences in power series expansions, and an axiomatic scheme underwriting such expansions. These schemes can be separated; in particular, the regularization scheme can be adopted by pragmatists independently of the axiomatic scheme (Helling 2012; Falk et al. 2010). Conversely, the axiomatic scheme can be adopted by purists to extend purist axiomatic systems to include perturbative techniques (Brunetti and Fredenhagen 2000).

  11. 11.

    The proof of this claim rests on the fact that it is always possible to choose two Lorentz transformations that time-order a Jost point (x 1, …, x n ) in opposite ways.

  12. 12.

    The first entailment is based on the fact that the time-ordering of two points is RLI unless the points are spacelike separated. Thus if a field is RLI, then so are time-ordered products of it, except when it is evaluated at spacelike separated points. But if the field commutes when it is evaluated at spacelike separated points, then time-ordering will not violate RLI even at such points. This also holds for sums of products of fields, and hence for ℋ int (x). The second entailment follows since if time-ordered products of ℋ int (x) are RLl, then so is the S-matrix in the form (1), since all other quantities in (1) are manifestly RLI.

  13. 13.

    Chaichian et al. (2011, p. 178) provide examples of non-local interaction Hamiltonian densities that are restricted Lorentz invariant and violate CPT invariance (thanks to a referee for pointing this out).

  14. 14.

    Here is another concern about the feasibility of Premise I in pragmatist approaches. If an interacting RQFT is in the business of calculating S-matrix elements, then τ-functions play an important role, as the discussion of the LSZ and Gell-Mann/Low formulas indicated, and this seems to make Premise I initially plausible. However, if there are other methods for calculating S-matrix elements that do not rely on τ-functions, and, moreover, if there are other testable predictions of RQFTs that can be derived without the use of τ-functions, then Premise I will again loose traction with pragmatists.

  15. 15.

    For the purist, this problem manifested itself in the fact that currently there are no examples of realistic interacting τ-functions in the form of well-defined analytic functions. For the pragmatist who allows τ-functions to take the form of divergent power series expansions obtained via the Gell-Mann/Low formula, the problem is that such expressions do not satisfy the Spectrum Condition (in the sense that the fields that occur in them do not satisfy the Spectrum Condition).

References

  • Arntzenius, F. (2011). The CPT theorem. In C. Callender (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of time (pp. 633–646). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bain, J. (2013). CPT invariance, the spin-statistics connection, and the ontology of relativistic quantum field theories. Erkenntnis, 78, 797–821.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, M. (2011). Lorentz violation in top-quark production and decay. In V. Kostelecky’ (Ed.), Proceedings of the 5th meeting on CPT and Lorentz Symmetry (pp. 179–183). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borchers, H., & Yngvason, J. (2001). On the PCT-theorem in the theory of local observables. In R. Longo (Ed.), Mathematical physics in mathematics and physics: Quantum and operator algebraic aspects (pp. 39–64). Providence: American Mathematical Society. Available online as arXiv:math-ph/0012020v1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouatta, N., & Butterfield, J. (2014). On emergence in gauge theories at the ’t Hooft limit. European Journal for Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1007/s13194-014-0098-1. Preprint. Available at http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/id/eprint/9288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunetti, R., & Fredenhagen, K. (2000). Microlocal analysis and interacting quantum field theories: Renormalization on physical backgrounds. Communications in Mathematical Physics, 208, 623–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chaichian, M., Dolgov, A., Novikov, V., & Tureanu, A. (2011). CPT violation does not lead to violation of lorentz invariance and vice versa. Physics Letters, B699, 177–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duncan, A. (2012). The conceptual framework of quantum field theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dütsch, M., & Gracia-Bondía, J. (2012). On the assertion that PCT violation implies Lorentz non-invariance. Physics Letters, B711, 428–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, S., Häußling, R., & Scheck, F. (2010). Renormalization in quantum field theory: An improved rigorous method. Journal of Physics, A43, 035401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, D. (2009). Quantum field theory: Underdetermination, inconsistency, and idealization. Philosophy of Science, 76, 536–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, D. (2011). How to take particle physics seriously: A further defense of axiomatic quantum field theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 42, 126–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greaves, H. (2010). Towards a geometrical understanding of the CPT theorem. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 27–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, O. (2002). CPT violation implies violation of Lorentz invariance. Physical Review Letters, 89, 231602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guido, D., & Longo, R. (1995). An algebraic spin and statistics theorem. Communications in Mathematical Physics, 172, 517–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagar, A. (2009). Minimal length in quantum gravity and the fate of Lorentz invariance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 40, 259–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helling, R. (2012). How I learned to stop worrying and love QFT (preprint), arXiv:1201.2714v2 [math-ph].

    Google Scholar 

  • Jost, R. (1957). Eine Bemerkung zum CTP theorem. Helvetica Physica Acta, 30, 409–416.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévy-Leblond, J.-M. (1967). Galilean quantum field theories and a ghostless Lee model. Communications in Mathematical Physics, 4, 157–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liberati, S. (2013). Tests of Lorentz invariance: A 2013 update. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 30, 133001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sozzi, M. (2008). Discrete symmetries and CP violation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Streater, R., & Wightman, A. (1964). PCT, spin and statistics, and all that. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Summers, S. (2012). A perspective on constructive quantum field theory (preprint), arXiv:1203.3991v1 [math-ph].

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2011). Taking particle physics seriously: A critique of the algebraic approach to quantum field theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 42, 116–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (1995). The quantum theory of fields (Vol. 1). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wightman, A. (1956). Quantum field theory in terms of vacuum expectation values. Physical Review, 101, 860–866.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan Bain .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bain, J. (2015). Pragmatists and Purists on CPT Invariance in Relativistic Quantum Field Theories. In: Mäki, U., Votsis, I., Ruphy, S., Schurz, G. (eds) Recent Developments in the Philosophy of Science: EPSA13 Helsinki. European Studies in Philosophy of Science, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-23015-3_17

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics