Skip to main content

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS,volume 2))

  • 616 Accesses

Abstract

Pluralism is a fringe position in debates about the metaphysics of mind as the large majority of philosophers endorse either physicalism or dualism. While my proposal of a pluralist theory of the mind contrasts with contemporary philosophy of mind, I argue that it shares many assumptions with philosophical positions that were popular in the nineteenth and early twentieth century. The aim of this chapter is to propose a historical diagnosis of the development of analytic philosophy of mind and of the exclusion of a wide range of positions that do not qualify as physicalism or dualism. I develop this historical diagnosis on the basis of the case study of Moritz Schlick’s monist parallelism. Schlick challenges both materialism and dualism by insisting that we can describe the world in terms of different but equally fundamental conceptual systems. Materialism is wrong in assuming the priority of the physical perspective, while dualism is mistaken in the assumption that two equally fundamental conceptual systems must refer to metaphysically distinct realms of reality. While this monist parallelism was the dominant position in German philosophy of mind from the late nineteenth to the early twentieth century, it disappeared with the rise of analytic philosophy of mind in the second half of the twentieth century. I argue that post-war philosophy of mind presupposed the “ontological priority of the physical” and left no room for alternative positions such as monist parallelism, pluralism, positivism, or idealism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Of course, the characterization of philosophy of mind as “normal science” should not be taken too seriously and follows a general trend to use Kuhn’s terminology to describe general features of academic discourse dynamics. Furthermore, it leaves the question open whether philosophers should aim at research that resembles “normal science” in the empirical sciences.

  2. 2.

    Examples include Braddon-Mitchell and Jackson (2007, 17–18), Campbell (2005, 28–30), and Heil (2012, 31–33). Braddon-Mitchell and Jackson nicely summarize the current attitude: “There are, as far as we know, no parallelists left. So we’ll pass over this implausible view” (18).

  3. 3.

    Gregory (1977) is an excellent (and the only) monograph on this materialist movement. See also Bayertz et al. (2012) for a helpful anthology.

References

  • Bayertz, Kurt, Myriam Gerhard, and Walter Jaeschke, eds. 2012. Der Materialismus-Streit. Hamburg: Meiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, Ned. 1997. Anti-Reductionism Slaps Back. Noûs 31 (s11): 107–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • du Bois-Reymond, Emil. 1872. Über die Grenzen des Naturerkennens. Leipzig: Von Veit & Com.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, David, and Frank Jackson. 2007. The Philosophy of Mind and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, Neil. 2005. A Brief Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Peterborough: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David. 2012. Constructing the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1970. Mental Events. In Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fechner, Gustav. 1851. Zend Avesta oder über die Dinge des Himmels und des Jenseits. Leipzig: L. Voss.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fechner, Gustav. 1860. Elemente der Psychophysik. Leipzig: Breitkopf und Härtel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, Herbert. 1967. The Mental and the Physical: The Essay and a Postscript. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Francescotti, Robert. 2014. Physicalism and the Mind. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, Kurt. 1934. Der Aufbau des Organismus. Den Haag: Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Nelson. 1978. Ways of Worldmaking. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, Frederick. 1977. Scientific Materialism in Nineteenth Century Germany. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heidelberger, Michael. 2004. Nature from Within: Gustav Theodor Fechner and His Psychophysical Worldview. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidelberger, Michael. 2006. Kantianism and Realism: Alois Riehl (and Moritz Schlick). In The Kantian Legacy in Nineteenth-Century Science, eds. Michael Friedman and Alfred Nordmann, 227–247. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil, John. 2012. Philosophy of Mind: A Contemporary Introduction. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, Christopher S., and Brian P. McLaughlin. 1999. There Are Fewer Things in Reality Than Are Dreamt of in Chalmers’ Philosophy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59: 448–449.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, Frank. 1982. Epiphenomenal Qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly 32: 12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Jaegwon. 2005. Physicalism, or Something Near Enough. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, Wolfgang. 1924. Bemerkungen zum Leib-Seele Problem. Deutsche Medizinische Wochenschrift 50: 1269–1270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loar, Brian. 1990. Phenomenal States. Philosophical Perspectives 4: 81–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, David. 2012. Language and Human Nature: Kurt Goldstein’s Neurolinguistic Foundations of a Holistic Philosophy. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 48 (1): 40–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, Moritz. General Theory of Knowledge. Vienna: Springer, 1918/1974.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, Moritz. Letter to Ernst Cassirer, 1927. Inv. No. 94. Schlick-Papers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, John JC. 1959. Sensations and Brain Processes. The Philosophical Review 68 (2): 141–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stubenberg, Leopold. 1997. Austria Vs. Australia: Two Versions of the Identity Theory. In Austrian Philosophy Past and Present, eds. Rudolf Haller, Keith Lehrer, and Johann Christian Marek, 125–46. Boston: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ludwig, D. (2015). A Historical Diagnosis. In: A Pluralist Theory of the Mind. European Studies in Philosophy of Science, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-22738-2_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics