Skip to main content

Preventing Assistance to Die: Assessing Indirect Paternalism Regarding Voluntary Active Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
New Directions in the Ethics of Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia

Part of the book series: International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine ((LIME,volume 64))

Abstract

The chapter focuses on cases of assisted suicide and voluntary euthanasia in relation to the rarely discussed notion of indirect paternalism. Indirect paternalism involves not just a paternalistic intervener and a person whose welfare is supposed to be protected, but also another party, whom I call “assistant.” Indirect paternalism interferes with an assistant in order to prevent harm to another person. I will introduce a strategy that paternalists can pursue to justify indirect paternalism. It specifically targets an element of assistance cases, namely the fact that people do not necessarily have a justified claim or entitlement to demand such assistance. To prevent people from providing assistance seems normatively different from preventing a person to do something to herself by her own means. I critically discuss arguments from the goals of medicine and from the conscientious objection. These aspects are not deemed decisive when considering the case of indirect paternalistic intervention. Finally, I argue against the rationale of indirect paternalism by showing that there are at least two situations where it does not succeed. One such situation that undermines the justification of indirect paternalism is present when the offered service is itself harmless, another pertinent situation consists of a person necessarily requiring assistance to be really free. At least in some cases, these very conditions are given when contemplating assistance to die.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This chapter draws on two other papers that focus on different problems but fall in the same area (Schramme 2013, 2015).

  2. 2.

    Though at least theoretically there might be multiple-party cases of paternalism that are not forms of indirect paternalism, see Feinberg ( 1986, 9). Feinberg used the term “two-party cases”, but this might be confusing as there are more than two parties involved in the practice of indirect paternalism. He obviously meant that two parties are the target of a paternalistic interference, where one party is interfered with and the other benefits.

  3. 3.

    Because B seems to harm A one might think that these cases were already banned by the Millian harm principle. Yet it should be obvious that the voluntary consent changes the normative status of the same action here and, as we will see, it is even slightly misleading to say that B harms A.

  4. 4.

    We could also say that impersonal harm is harm for a person, but only personal harm is harm to a person.

  5. 5.

    Note that it is even possible to accept that impersonal harm is intrinsically bad, and still allow for other considerations, which have to do with personal interests, to outweigh this kind of harm and to conclude that there is no personal harm present where a person has an interest in an impersonal harm. A person may reasonably choose what is intrinsically bad, as long at it is not only intrinsically bad.

  6. 6.

    It is indeed arguable whether soft paternalism should be called “paternalism” at all (see Feinberg 1986, 12). But even if intervention into non-voluntary choices were not paternalism after all, this would of course still allow us to regard the cases we now refer to under the umbrella term “soft paternalism” as unjustified.

  7. 7.

    Obviously it is an important issue what kind of undue influences there might be, which consequently undermine consent to (impersonal) harm. I cannot discuss this question here, but see, for instance, Kleinig ( 2010, 13 ff.).

  8. 8.

    In these cases we might also want to use the notion “autonomous choice”. I disregard the relation between autonomy and voluntariness for the purposes of this essay.

  9. 9.

    There is an important debate regarding the possible coerciveness of inducements that I will ignore for the purposes of this chapter (see, for instance, Radcliffe 2010).

  10. 10.

    This is an important insight that is often ignored, for instance by Feinberg (see Hirsch 2008 and du Bois-Pedain 2010).

  11. 11.

    Surely one may want to insist that the consent given by a person to the service of the assistant is normatively sufficient to justify providing assistance. Indeed, this seems to follow from the logic of the volenti principle. But one aspect of my chapter is to show why assuming a normatively different status of indirect paternalism is plausible and that the volenti principle cannot be an absolute principle.

  12. 12.

    I take ‘claim’ to be a moral notion here. It can be seen as a moral right, but I avoid the terminology to prevent confusion with legal rights. A person might have a legal entitlement to all kinds of morally dubious services, but these contracts are not my concern here, rather whether those contracts should be allowed. I also take ‘claim’ as to imply a duty of others to refrain from interference, so it is not just a ‘liberty’, in the Hohfeldian sense (Hohfeld 1923), where a person has permission to do something and hence is not doing something wrong. A justified claim, or entitlement, as such, does not include a duty of others to provide necessary means to pursue a goal, but I want to consider later how far such provision might indeed be morally required.

  13. 13.

    Though we might want to introduce bans on, say, the aggressive marketing of sweets.

  14. 14.

    In contrast, Hill (2014, 277), in a recent contribution to a companion asserts: “Thus if suicide is not immoral in certain cases, then it will be permissible for others to assist unless there are further arguments against this.” (Emphasis in original.) It might be worth stressing that I do not want to argue that an assistant’s help to kill a person might be itself morally wrong, but that the case for an entitlement to such service needs to be made.

  15. 15.

    Some people might want to say that I am conceding far too much to the paternalist, as anti-paternalists would maintain that service users always have a claim right, if not to the provision of services, but to purchase services on a free market. In addition they might want to say that service providers have the right to sell their services, as long as these are neither immoral nor illegal. But this argument relies (a) on the ideology of the free market, a topic I would like to avoid, and (b) on a liberal reading of what might be regarded as immoral—namely only services that cause personal harm to others. My aim here is to scrutinize the paternalist strategy in relation to indirect paternalism without begging the question in favor of a strongly liberal, or even libertarian, point of view, although I have of course already hinted at certain aspects of a liberal viewpoint that seem to me unavoidable.

  16. 16.

    This difference might not be significant in practice, after all, in case of assistance to die, as it is normally not discussed or in reality offered as a paid service. If indeed those services would only be affordable for rich people, this might lead to injustice. I disregard the issue of payments in this chapter.

  17. 17.

    Many paternalists support intervention into choices only where it enhances autonomy. Some paternalists have a particular, more demanding, reading of the concept of autonomy, which does not comply with the interpretation I endorse (but see Cholbi (2013a, b), for an important alternative).

  18. 18.

    I prefer the term “real liberty”, because it has been used in related discussions, especially in Philippe van Parijs’s book Real Freedom for All (1995). Occasionally “positive liberty” is also used in the debate, but it might cause some confusion with another notion of positive liberty that was discussed in a famous essay by Isaiah Berlin (2002).

  19. 19.

    This formulation is less complicated than it should be. We might want to add that people should only be at liberty to do what they want to do when sufficiently informed, when no coercing influences are present, and so on.

  20. 20.

    Thanks to Michael Cholbi for raising this issue.

References

  • Bergelson, Vera. 2010. Consent to harm. In The ethics of consent: Theory and practice, eds. Franklin G. Miller and Alan Wertheimer, 163–192. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, Isaiah. 2002. Two concepts of liberty. In Liberty: Incorporating four essays on liberty, ed. Henry Hardy, 166–217. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cholbi, Michael J. 2013a. Kantian paternalism and suicide intervention. In Paternalism: Theory and practice, eds. Christian Coons and Michael E. Weber, 115–133. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cholbi, Michael J. 2013b. The terminal, the futile, and the psychiatrically disordered. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 36: 498–505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Du Bois-Pedain, Antje. 2010. Die Beteiligung an fremder Selbstschädigung als eigenständiger Typus moralisch relevanten Verhaltens—Ein Beitrag zur Strukturanalyse des indirekten Paternalismus. In Paternalismus im Strafrecht: Die Kriminalisierung von selbstschädigendem Verhalten, eds. Andrew von Hirsch, Ulfrid Neumann, and Kurt Seelmann eds., 33–56. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Joel. 1986. Harm to self: The moral limits of the criminal law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, Thomas E. 2014. Killing ourselves. In Cambridge companion to life and death, ed. Steven Luper, 264–281. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, Andreas von. 2008. Direct paternalism: Criminalizing self-injurious conduct. Criminal Justice Ethics 27: 25–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohfeld, Wesley N. 1923. Fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleinig, John. 2010. The nature of consent. In The ethics of consent: Theory and practice, eds. Franklin G. Miller and Alan Wertheimer, 3–24. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Möller, Kai. 2005. Paternalismus und Persönlichkeitsrecht. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Möller, Kai. 2009. Two conceptions of positive liberty: Towards an autonomy-based theory of constitutional rights. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 29: 757–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oshana, Marina A.L. 2003. How much should we value autonomy? Social Philosophy and Policy 20: 99–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radcliffe, Janet Richards. 2010. Consent with inducement: The case of body parts and services. In The ethics of consent: Theory and practice, eds. Franklin G. Miller and Alan Wertheimer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schramme, Thomas. 2013. Rational suicide, assisted suicide, and indirect legal paternalism. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 36: 477–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schramme, Thomas. 2015. Contested services, indirect paternalism and autonomy as real liberty. In New perspectives on paternalism and health care, ed. Thomas Schramme. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Simester, Andrew P., and Andreas Von Hirsch. 2011. Crimes, harms, and wrongs: On the principles of criminalisation. Oxford and Portland, Oregon: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Schramme .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schramme, T. (2015). Preventing Assistance to Die: Assessing Indirect Paternalism Regarding Voluntary Active Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide. In: Cholbi, M., Varelius, J. (eds) New Directions in the Ethics of Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia. International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine, vol 64. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-22050-5_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics