Skip to main content

Beliefs about the nature of numbers

  • Chapter
Mathematics, Substance and Surmise

Abstract

Nearly all psychologists think that cardinality is the basis of number knowledge. When they test infants’ sensitivity to number, they look for evidence that the infants grasp the cardinality of groups of physical objects. And when they test older children’s understanding of the meaning of number words, they look for evidence that the children can, for example, “Give [the experimenter] three pencils” or can “Point to the picture of four balloons.” But when people think about the positive integers, do they single them out by means of the numbers’ cardinality, by means of the ordinal relations that hold among them, or in some other way? This chapter reviews recent research in cognitive psychology that compares people’s judgments about the integers’ cardinal and ordinal properties. It also presents new experimental evidence suggesting that, at least for adults, the integers’ cardinality is less central than their number-theoretic and arithmetic properties.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This issue might be put by asking whether people think of the first few naturals as cardinal or ordinal numbers. However, “cardinal number” and “ordinal number” have special meanings in set theory, and these meanings don’t provide the intended contrast. In their usual development (e.g., [8]), the ordinals and cardinals do not differ in the finite range, with which we will be concerned in this chapter. (Both ordinal and cardinal numbers include transfinite numbers—for which they do differ—and so extend beyond the natural numbers.)

  2. 2.

    You might wonder about the use of sets in this construction: Do young children have a notion of set that’s comparable to mathematicians’ sets? Attributing to children at this age a concept of set in the full-blooded sense would be fatal to Carey’s claim that Quinian bootstrapping produces new primitive concepts (e.g., the concept FIVE) that can’t in principle be expressed in terms of the child’s pre-bootstrap vocabulary. We know how to express FIVE in terms of sets (see, e.g., [8]). So the notion of set implicit in representations like {object 1 , object 2 } is presumably more restrictive than ordinary sets.

  3. 3.

    Many quantitative contexts, including some just mentioned, involve measurement of continuous dimensions (e.g., temperature, time, and length) rather than counting. Current research in developmental psychology suggests that infants are about equally sensitive to the number of objects in a collection (for n > 3) and to the continuous extent (e.g., area) of a single object when it is presented alone (see [9] for an overview). This is presumably because the same kind of psychophysical mechanism handles both types of information (see Section 3.1). However, infants’ accuracy for the number of objects in a collection (again, for n > 3) is better than that for the continuous extent of the objects in the same collection [5]. Of course, children’s knowledge of continuous extent, like their knowledge of number, has to undergo further changes before it can support adult uses of measurement (see, e.g., [24]). Some intricate issues exist about children’s understanding of continuous quantity that are the topic of current research [39], but because this chapter focuses on knowledge of natural numbers, this brief summary will have to do.

  4. 4.

    The same is true in education theory, as Sinclair points out in her chapter in this volume. See that chapter for an alternative that is more in line with the structural perspective.

References

  1. W.P. Banks, M. Fujii and F. Kayra-Stuart, “Semantic congruity effects in comparative judgments of magnitudes of digits,” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, vol. 2 (1976) 435–447.

    Google Scholar 

  2. P.B. Buckley and C.B. Gillman, “Comparisons of digits and dot patterns,” Journal of Experimental Psychology, vol. 103 (1974) 1131–1136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. S. Carey, The origin of concepts, Oxford University Press, New York, NY, 2009.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  4. L. Carroll, Alice’s adventures in wonderland, Macmillan and Co., London, 1866.

    Google Scholar 

  5. S. Cordes and E.M. Brannon, “Attending to one of many: When infants are surprisingly poor at discriminating an item’s size,” Frontiers in Psychology, vol. 2 (2011) doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2011.00065.

  6. K. Davidson, K. Eng and D. Barner, “Does learning to count involve a semantic induction?,” Cognition, vol. 123 (2012) 162–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. S. Dehaene, The number sense: how mathematical knowledge is embedded in our brains, Oxford University Press, New York, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  8. K. Devlin, The joy of sets, 2nd ed., Springer, Berlin, 1993.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. L. Feigenson, “The equality of quantity,” Trends in Cognitive Sciences, vol. 11 (2007) 185–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. M.S. Franklin, J. Jonides and E.E. Smith, “Processing of order information for numbers and months,” Memory & Cognition, vol. 37 (2009) 644–654.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. G. Frege, The foundations of arithmetic: A logico-mathematical enquiry into the concept of number, 2nd rev. ed., Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  12. K.C. Fuson, Children’s counting and concepts of number, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1988.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  13. R. Gelman and C.R. Gallistel, The child’s understanding of number, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  14. C. Hanlon, “The emergence of set-relational quantifiers in early childhood”, in: The development of language and language researchers: Essays in honor of Roger Brown, F.S. Kessel, ed., Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc, Hillsdale, NJ, 1988, pp. 65–78.

    Google Scholar 

  15. P.M. Hartnett, “The development of mathematical insight: From one, two, three to infinity,” Dissertation Abstracts International, vol. 52 (1992) 3921.

    Google Scholar 

  16. R.G. Heck Jr, “Cardinality, counting, and equinumerosity,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, vol. 41 (2000) 187–209.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  17. R.G. Heck Jr, “Frege’s theorem: An overview”, in: Frege’s theorem, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, 2011, pp. 1–39.

    Google Scholar 

  18. V. Izard, A. Streri and E.S. Spelke, “Toward exact number: Young children use one-to-one correspondence to measure set identity but not numerical equality,” Cognitive Psychology, vol. 72 (2014) 27–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. D.H. Krantz, R.D. Luce, P. Suppes and A. Tversky, Foundations of measurement, Academic Press, New York, 1971.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. M. Le Corre, “Children acquire the later-greater principle after the cardinal principle,” British Journal of Developmental Psychology, vol. 32 (2014) 163–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Ø. Linnebo, “The individuation of the natural numbers”, in: New waves in philosophy of mathematics, O. Bueno, Ø. Linnebo, eds., Palgrave, Houndmills, UK, 2009, pp. 220–238.

    Google Scholar 

  22. I.M. Lyons and S.L. Beilock, “Ordinality and the nature of symbolic numbers,” The Journal of Neuroscience, vol. 33 (2013) 17052–17061.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. J. MacFarlane, “Double vision: two questions about the neo-Fregean program,” Synthese, vol. 170 (2009) 443–456.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  24. K.F. Miller, “Measurement as a tool for thought: The role of measuring procedures in children’s understanding of quantitative invariance,” Developmental Psychology, vol. 25 (1989) 589–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. K.S. Mix, J. Huttenlocher and S.C. Levine, Quantitative development in infancy and early childhood, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, 2002.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  26. R.S. Moyer and S.T. Dumais, “Mental comparison,” Psychology of Learning and Motivation, vol. 12 (1978) 117–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. R.S. Moyer and T.K. Landauer, “Time required for judgements of numerical inequality,” Nature, vol. 215 (1967) 1519–1520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. C. Parsons, Mathematical thought and its objects, Cambridge University Press, New York, 2008.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. S.T. Piantadosi, J.B. Tenenbaum and N.D. Goodman, “Bootstrapping in a language of thought: A formal model of numerical concept learning,” Cognition, vol. 123 (2012) 199–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. M.D. Resnik, Mathematics as a science of patterns, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, 1997.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  31. G. Rey, “Innate and learned: Carey, Mad Dog nativism, and the poverty of stimuli and analogies (yet again),” Mind & Language, vol. 29 (2014) 109–132.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  32. L.J. Rips, “Bootstrapping: How not to learn”, in: Encyclopedia of the sciences of learning, N.M. Seel, ed., Springer, Berlin, 2012, pp. 473–477.

    Google Scholar 

  33. L.J. Rips, “How many is a zillion? Sources of number distortion,” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, vol. 39 (2013) 1257–1264.

    Google Scholar 

  34. L.J. Rips, Lines of thought: Central concepts in cognitive psychology, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, 2011.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  35. L.J. Rips, J. Asmuth and A. Bloomfield, “Can statistical learning bootstrap the integers?” Cognition, vol. 128 (2013) 320–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. L.J. Rips, J. Asmuth and A. Bloomfield, “Do children learn the integers by induction?” Cognition, vol. 106 (2008) 940–951.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. L.J. Rips, J. Asmuth and A. Bloomfield, “Giving the boot to the bootstrap: How not to learn the natural numbers,” Cognition, vol. 101 (2006) B51-B60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. L.J. Rips, A. Bloomfield and J. Asmuth, “From numerical concepts to concepts of number,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences, vol. 31 (2008) 623–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. L.J. Rips and S.J. Hespos, “Divisions of the physical world: Concepts of objects and substances,” Psychological Bulletin, vol. 141 (2015).

    Google Scholar 

  40. F.S. Roberts, Measurement theory with applications to decisionmaking, utility, and the social sciences, Addison-Wesley, Reading, Mass., 1979.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  41. B. Russell, Introduction to mathematical philosophy, Allen & Unwin, London, 1919.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  42. B.W. Sarnecka and C.E. Wright, “The idea of an exact number: Children’s understanding of cardinality and equinumerosity,” Cognitive Science, vol. 37 (2013) 1493–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. S. Shapiro, Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology, Oxford University Press, New York, 1997.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  44. E. Turconi, J.I.D. Campbell and X. Seron, “Numerical order and quantity processing in number comparison,” Cognition, vol. 98 (2006) 273–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. H.M. Wellman and K.F. Miller, “Thinking about nothing: Development of concepts of zero,” British Journal of Developmental Psychology, vol. 4 (1986) 31–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. K. Wynn, “Children’s acquisition of the number words and the counting system,” Cognitive Psychology, vol. 24 (1992) 220–251.

    Google Scholar 

  47. E.N. Zalta, “Frege’s theorem and foundations for arithmetic”, in: Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, E.N. Zalta, ed., 2014.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

Thanks to Ernest Davis, Jacob Dink, and Nicolas Leonard for comments on an earlier version of this chapter and to John Glines, Jane Ko, and Gabrielle McCarthy for their help with the experiments described in Section 4.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lance J. Rips .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rips, L.J. (2015). Beliefs about the nature of numbers. In: Davis, E., Davis, P. (eds) Mathematics, Substance and Surmise. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-21473-3_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics