Skip to main content

The linguistic status of mathematics

  • Chapter
Mathematics, Substance and Surmise
  • 1291 Accesses

Abstract

Mathematicians have often discussed mathematics as a language. Common linguistic categories have analogous mathematical objects. A comparison of linguistic categories and mathematical objects is developed with reference to the early history of mathematics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The initial proposal of Lincos most closely approximated the aphorism in its claim that “mathematical expressions and formulae belong to a language different from that of the surrounding context…The syntactical structure of ‘mathematical language’ differs enormously from that of all natural languages” [16, p. 6].

  2. 2.

    For the initial proposal of Astraglossa, see [22]. Hogben presumed the recipients of the messages to be Martians and Astraglossa depends on two-way communication. Hogben most nearly approximated the aphorism by writing that “[n]umber will initially be our common idiom of reciprocal recognition; and astronomy will be the topic of our first factual conversations” [22, p. 260].

  3. 3.

    For example, the order of operations suggests that in 7 × (3 + 2) the addition happens before the multiplication. Independent mathematical statements exist outside of a temporal framework. Without a context established by natural language, the mathematical statements \(6 + 2 = 8\) and 7 × 5 = 35 have no relationship to each other. In contrast, natural languages can often easily suggest a temporal relationship, such as “Six was increased by two to make eight; Seven will be multiplied by five to find thirty-five.”

  4. 4.

    By contrast, the category of Babylonian and Egyptian operations is clopen. Both categories are closed because new Babylonian or Egyptian mathematical texts cannot be created but they are also open because new texts might be discovered or the reconstructions might be reassessed. For example, Plimpton 322 has yielded recent surprises.

  5. 5.

    Popular histories of mathematics often reproduce weakly cited counter-evidence. According to one edition, Chapter 64 of the Book of the Dead tallies 4,601,200 gods [4, p. 164]. Other editions confirm only one million. A grapheme introduced in the Ptolemaic era may express a sense of totality, or cyclical completion [40, p. 12, n. 6], or it may stand for millions, thereby increasing the old grapheme of the god Ḥeḥ to tens of millions [21, p. 280]. Occasionally, decorative hieroglyphs combine the graphemes of large numbers into images which may be read as “a hundred thousand million years” or even “ten million hundred thousand million years” [5, p. 507, s.v. ḥeḥ], but these graphemes are more likely artistic hyperbole than mathematical quantity.

  6. 6.

    The fraction \(\frac{2} {3}\) appears idiosyncratically as the only portion of an Egyptian number which is not easily classified as either an integer or an inverse. (The fraction \(\frac{5} {6}\) is sometimes cited as another example but this fraction is actually a ligature of \(\frac{2} {3}\) and \(\frac{1} {6}\).) This idiosyncrasy may be resolved by morphology. The fraction \(\frac{2} {3}\) was vocalized as rwy, a grammatical dual which literally means “the two parts.” The grapheme is better interpreted as \(\frac{1} {3} + \frac{1} {3}\) rather than a ratio of 2 to 3.

  7. 7.

    The naked inclusion of non-Western languages too often provokes consternation. The phrase may be transliterated as “kō ha sosū da to ı̄mashō” and translated as “Let’s say that is a prime.” The grapheme derives from a pictogram of hands braiding raw silk and the semantic range of the sign includes plain, poor, foundation, and root. The use of as a variable is admittedly somewhat contrived for modern Japanese. Probably, a variable from the Roman alphabet would be used, most likely a in slight contrast to the Western preference for p. Mathematics has become an international endeavor.

  8. 8.

    The obvious exception is Indian mathematics which has developed an overabundance of mathematical synonyms. Because Indian mathematical texts are almost exclusively poetic, these variations may be explained by causa metris. However, in many cases, this explanation is facile. To date, a systematic study of whether the variation in vocabulary of Indian mathematics remains a desideratum. Only careful comparison will reveal if these variations indicate regional variations, the temporal development of Sanskrit, or nuances among mathematical objects.

References

  1. A. Adler. Mathematics and creativity. The New Yorker, 47(53):39–45, feb 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  2. L. Bloomfield. An introduction to the study of language. H. Holt, 1914.

    Google Scholar 

  3. M. Brose. Die mittelägyptische nfr-pw-negation. Zeitschrift für Ägyptische Sprache und Altertumskunde, 136(1):1–7, aug 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  4. E. A. T. W. Budge. The Gods of the Egyptians. Methuen, London, 1904.

    Google Scholar 

  5. E. A. T. W. Budge. An egyptian hieroglyphic dictionary, volume 1. John Murray, London, 1920.

    Google Scholar 

  6. C. K. Caldwell and Y. Xiong. What is the smallest prime? Journal of Integer Sequences, 15(9), 2012. Article 12.9.7 and arXiv:1209.2007.

    Google Scholar 

  7. A. B. Chace. The Rhind mathematical papyrus: British Museum 10057 and 10058. Mathematical Association of America, Oberlin, 1929.

    Google Scholar 

  8. J.-P. Changeux and A. Connes. Conversations on mind, matter, and mathematics. Princeton University Press, 1995.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. E. C. Cherry, M. Halle, and R. Jakobson. Toward the logical description of languages in their phonemic aspect. Language, 29(1):34–46, 1953.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. P. J. Davis. The thread: a mathematical yarn. Birkhäuser, Boston, first edition, 1983.

    Google Scholar 

  11. P. J. Davis and R. Hersh. The mathematical experience. Birkhäuser, Boston, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  12. R. M. W. Dixon. Basic Linguistic Theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2010–2012.

    Google Scholar 

  13. T. W. R. E. L. Kaufman, M. W. Lord and J. Volkmann. The discrimination of visual number. The American Journal of Psychology, 62(4):498–525, oct 1949.

    Google Scholar 

  14. J. Evelyn. Sculptura, or, The history, and art of chalcography and engraving in copper. G. Beedle and T. Collins, Oxford, 1662.

    Google Scholar 

  15. J.-B.-J. Fourier. Théorie analytique de la chaleur. F. Didot, 1822.

    Google Scholar 

  16. H. Freudenthal. Lincos; design of a language for cosmic intercourse. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam, 1960.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. J. Friberg. Unexpected links between Egyptian and Babylonian mathematics. World Scientific, 2005.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. N. E. Fuchs, H. F. Hofmann, and R. Schwitter. Specifying logic programs in controlled natural language. In Specifying logic programs in controlled natural language, volume 94.17 of Berichte des Instituts für Informatik der Universität Zürich; Institut für Informatik der Universität Zürich, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  19. G. Galilei. Il saggiatore. Giacomo Mascardi, Rome, 1623.

    Google Scholar 

  20. K. Gödel. The consistency of the axiom of choice and of the generalized continuum-hypothesis with the axioms of set theory. Annals of mathematics studies. Princeton University Press, Oxford, 1940.

    Google Scholar 

  21. B. Gunn. Notices of recent publications. The Journal of Egyptian Archaeology, 3(4):279–286, oct 1916.

    Google Scholar 

  22. L. Hogben. Astraglossa, or first steps in celestial syntax. Journal of the British Interplanetary Society, 11(6):258–274, nov 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  23. J. Høyrup. Lengths, widths, surfaces: a portrait of old Babylonian algebra and its kin. Sources and studies in the history of mathematics and physical sciences. Springer, New York, 2002.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  24. T. Jech. Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded. Springer Monographs in Mathematics. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg New York, 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  25. B. Lumpkin. Africa in the mainstream of mathematics. In A. B. Powell and M. Frankenstein, editors, Ethnomathematics: challenging eurocentrism in mathematics education, SUNY series, reform in mathematics education., pages 101–118. State University of New York Press, Albany, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Y. I. Manin. Good proofs are proofs that make us wiser. In M. Aigne, editor, Berlin intelligencer: International Congress of Mathematicians, Mitteilungen der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung, page 16–19, Berlin, aug 1999. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  27. O. Neugebauer. Mathematische Keilschrift-Texte, volume 1 of Quellen und Studien zur Geschichte der Mathematik, Astronomie und Physik. J. Springer, Berlin, 1935.

    Google Scholar 

  28. T. E. Peet. The Rhind mathematical papyrus, British museum 10057 and 10058. The University Press of Liverpool and Hodder & Stoughton, London, 1923.

    Google Scholar 

  29. C. Proust. Mesopotamian metrological lists and tables:forgotten sources. In F. Bretelle-Establet, editor, Looking at It from Asia: The Processes that Shaped the Sources of History of Science, volume 265 of Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, pages 245–276. Springer, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  30. J. Ritter. Closing the eye of horus: The rise and fall of horus-eye fractions. In J. M. Steele and A. Imhausen, editors, Under One Sky: Astronomy and Mathematics in the Ancient Near East, volume 297 of Alter Orient und Altes Testament, pages 297–323. Ugarit-Verlag, Münster, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  31. M. Rukeyser. A turning wind, chapter Gibbs. The Viking Press, 1939.

    Google Scholar 

  32. M. Rukeyser. Willard Gibbs. Doubleday, Doran & Company, 1942.

    Google Scholar 

  33. R. P. Runyon, A. Haber, and P. Reese. Student workbook to accompany Fundamentals of behavioral statistics. Addison-Wesley Publishing Company, fourth edition, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  34. C. Sagan. The cosmic connection: an extraterrestrial perspective. Anchor Press, Garden City, NY, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  35. C. Sagan. The recognition of extraterrestrial intelligence. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences, 189(1095):143–153, may 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  36. C. Sagan. Cosmos. Random House, New York, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  37. C. Sagan. Contact: a novel. Simon and Schuster, New York, 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  38. R. Schofield. Sampling in historical research. In E. Wrigley, editor, Nineteenth-century society: essays in the use of quantitative methods for the study of social data, Cambridge Group for the History of Population and Social Structure, pages 146–190. Cambridge University Press, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  39. R. L. E. Schwarzenberger. The language of geometry. Mathematical Spectrum, 4(2):63–68, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  40. K. Sethe. Von Zahlen und Zahlworten bei den alten Ägyptern und was für andere Völker und Sprachen daraus zu lernern ist. K. J. Trübner, Strassburg, 1916.

    Google Scholar 

  41. J. Thomson. Britain: being the fourth part of Liberty, a poem. A. Millar, Oxford, 1736.

    Google Scholar 

  42. F. Viète. In artem analyticem isagoge. Mettayer, Tours, 1591.

    Google Scholar 

  43. N. West. Miss Lonelyhearts, a novel. New Directions Books, 1933.

    Google Scholar 

  44. L. Wheeler. Josiah Willard Gibbs, the history of a great mind. Yale University Press, New Haven, 1951.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  45. E. T. Whittaker and G. Robinson. The calculus of observations; a treatise on numerical mathematics,. Blackie and Son Limited, London, first edition, 1924.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Academics frequently praise books, but scholarly reflections seldom suit the tastes or developmental needs of children. Michel de Montaigne seems apt to inspire future Nietzsches when he declares that “obsession is the wellspring of genius and madness.” In contrast, [10] by Philip Davis allows those who doubt their genius but prize their sanity to pafnuty, that is, “to pursue tangential matters with hobby-like zeal.” Children as young as eleven have been known to incorporate pafnutying into their pedagogical formation. Through this slim volume, Davis tames madness with whimsy and humanizes genius by levity. Should an early exposure to the admixture of language and mathematics distract the student, that is, if the child becomes a recidivist pafnutier, youthful exuberance may be regulated by [11]. If the present argument resembles too much Montaigne’s madness or Davis’ skeptical classicist, it must be realized that despite several introductions and a shared institutional affiliation, this offering did not result from tutelage under Davis. Rather, it is offered as an homage to a past and present inspiration.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Micah T. Ross .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ross, M.T. (2015). The linguistic status of mathematics. In: Davis, E., Davis, P. (eds) Mathematics, Substance and Surmise. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-21473-3_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics