Skip to main content

Impure ‘de se’ Thoughts and Pragmatics (and How This Is Relevant to Pragmatics and IEM)

  • Chapter
Indirect Reports and Pragmatics

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 5))

Abstract

I shall start with some generic considerations on the pragmatics of ‘de se’ thoughts and I will then move on to the distinction between pure and impure ‘de se’ thoughts, which clearly involve some pragmatic discriminatory ability. Since impure ‘de se’ thoughts need not be IEM, it must be clear that IEM is not a semantic characteristic of psychological predicates but is available only after intervention of some pragmatic considerations. Anyway, the issue of IEM is to be considered as only tangential to the issue of ‘de se’ and thus, I will only reserve a final section for the definitive demonstration that IEM applies to certain psychological predicates only in the background of contextual considerations. IEM, in other words, is only pragmatic in nature. Although this is an important conclusion, it is deduced merely as a consequence of the analysis of ‘de se’ thoughts. The D-tour we are making is considerable, but not improper and without consequences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    ‘Purity’ in connection with reference unmediated by some descriptive component is a term used by García-Carpintero (2013, 76). Reasonably enough, the term ‘impure’ has been coined by myself in opposition to such a term.

  2. 2.

    I am largely following Higginbotham (2003) in the thought that there is a connection between ‘de se’ thoughts and IEM.

  3. 3.

    As Recanati (2012) says, “to be immune to error through misidentification, a first-person judgment must be truly subjective. The subject must not be thought of as an object which one identifies as oneself; for, if it is, the judgment rests on an identity (‘b = myself’) and is subject to identification errors”.

  4. 4.

    The source of information may come from inside the body (proprioceptive information, as ‘I feel a pain in my leg’ (see Recanati 2012) or from the flow of throught (inside the mind).

  5. 5.

    García-Carpintero (2013, 80) says that “the amnesiac cases suggest also that descriptive individuators, whether or not they allow for for ‘de re’ thought on the strictures of N, are unnecessary, for amnesiacs are able to think about themselves in a fully self-conscious way by using and understanding ‘I’ and related expressions for first-personal reference while ignoring everything about themselves”. However, this looks like a simplification. When I discuss Kant’s transcendental self, I present data to the effect that the ‘I’ must keep a file of what he said before to monitor his own speech for contradiction. Thus a truly amnesiac subject which only retains the ‘I’ mode of presentation of himself cannot successfully embark on the enterprise of making a coherent discourse devoid of contradictions. It is necessary that the ‘I’ should always come accompanied by a file on what he has said before.

  6. 6.

    García-Carpintero (2013) says that “believers in a substantive singular/general distinction will have to accept that some ‘de re’ ascriptions (those meeting Quine’s criterion) report what in fact are general thoughts and viceversa…”.

  7. 7.

    ‘Am I John Smith’ and ‘I am John Smith’ would have to share a neutral (or minimal) mode of presentation of ‘I’. But this neutral mode of presentation needs saturating information in the question ‘Am I John Smith?’, while in the answer the information in the predicate comes through antecedent knowledge that the speaker knows the identity of the subject.

  8. 8.

    Where the apposition ‘John Perry’ may be an implicit constituent, something one does not have an occurrent thought of (to use words by Davis) but one could have an occurrent thought of, had one a chance to make this constituent explicit.

  9. 9.

    Rosenthal (in a p.c.) writes the following:

    You assert that the I in the the ‘I think’ that Kant thinks must be able to go with every thought is not a sequence of tokens of the mental analogue of ‘I’, but something that has the capacity to tie all one’s thoughts together.

    I certainly agree that that’s something like what Kant had in mind. But there’s a question about whether any such thing is there to be had. Simply stipulating that there is a mental item that will do the relevant unifying job doesn’t show that there is any such mental item.

    Note in that connection Kant’s methodology: Establishing what is necessary for what is actual even to be possible. Kant takes the relevant unity of the self through time and across thoughts to be actual. He therefore argues that a unifying ‘I’ is necessary for that unity even to be possible.

    That’s fine – except that assuming that strong unity – we might in the context of my own article call it a thick unity – is question begging. I argue that there is an appearance of such strong unity, but that we have no reason to suppose that that strong unity is also real, in addition to being apparent.

    My reply to Rosenthal is that from a philosophical point of view, I am certainly sympathetic to Kant’s considerations, which derive, on a priori grounds, the unity of different slices of the thinking subject. However, in a linguistic paper, like the present one, not as much as this is required. We can be sympathetic with Rosenthal that only a thin identification is required, as this may well occur through anaphoricity, that is to say coindexation. Coindexation need not involve stipulation, but is normally a pragmatic interpretative matter (the hearer associates the ‘I’ of a thought with the producer of that thought and then anaphorically links one ‘I’ to the next). Of course, the thinking subject need not interpret occurrences of ‘I’ (in his own thoughts) as anaphorically linked. They are are already linked by the fact that they are uttered by the same voice (if just thought is considered, we may just assume that the thinker remembers whether his thoughts are his own and coindexes the ‘I’s of his thoughts with his own thoughts, from which it follows that the different occurrences of ‘I’ of his thoughts refer to the same person).

  10. 10.

    Rosenthal (in a p.c.) replies that the case of a person who cares (or actually manages) not to contradict herself is pretty rare. I agree with that. I agree that people can change their minds, over time. However, there are cases to conform to the one I have described, such as that of the rational law-maker who has to avoid and eliminate contradictions (Dascal 2003; Capone 2013). There are, furthermore, also contexts in which one is held to certain assumptions, as in the course of a logical demonstration.

References

  • Bezuidenhout, A. (1997). Pragmatics, semantic under-determination and the referential/attributive distinction. Mind, 106(423), 375–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2007). Postscript to ‘Belief de re’. In T. Burge (Ed.), Foundations of mind (pp. 65–81). Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (1999). Immunity to error through misidentification and the meaning of a referring term. Philosophical Topics, 66(1), 89–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2010). Between Scylla and Charybdis: The semantics and pragmatics of attitudes ‘de se’. Intercultural Pragmatics, 7(3), 471–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2013). The role of pragmatics in (re)constructing the rational law-maker. Pragmatics and Cognition, 21(2), 399–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2006). The architecture of the mind. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2002). Thoughts and utterances. The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N. (1966). “He”: A study in the logic of self-consciousness. Ratio, 8, 130–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coliva, A. (2003). The first person: Error through misidentification, the split between speaker’s and semantic reference and the real guarantee. Journal of Philosophy, 100(8), 416–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummings, L. (2009). Clinical pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, M. (2003). Interpretation and understanding. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis Wayne, A. (2013). Indexicals and ‘de se’ attitudes. In Attitudes de se. Linguistics, epistemology, metaphysics (pp. 29–58). Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2013). The myth of the problematic ‘de se’. In N. Feit & A. Capone (Eds.), Attitudes de se. Linguistics, epistemology, metaphysics (pp. 133–162). Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2010). The pragmatics of belief. Journal of Pragmatics, 42, 35–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2013). The epistemology of ‘de se’ beliefs. In N. Feit & A. Capone (Eds.), Attitudes de se: Linguistics, epistemology and metaphysics. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • García-Carpintero, M. (2013). Self-conception: Sosa on ‘de se’ thought. In J. Turri (Ed.), Virtuous thoughts: The philosophy of Ernest Sosa (pp. 73–99). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (2003). Remembering, imagining, and the first person. In A. Barber (Ed.), Epistemology of language (pp. 496–535). Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howell, R. J. (2007). Immunity to error and subjectivity. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 37(4), 581–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Y. (2007). Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Y. (2013). De se’ attitude/belief ascription and Neo-Gricean truth-conditional pragmatics. Logophoric expressions in West African languages and long-distance reflexives in East, South, and Southeast Asian languages. In N. Feit & A. Capone (Eds.), Attitudes de se. Linguistics, epistemology, metaphysics (pp. 185–210). Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaszczolt, K. (2013). Contextualism and minimalism on ‘de se’ belief ascription. In N. Feit & A. Capone (Eds.), Attitudes de se. Linguistics, epistemology, metaphysics (pp. 69–103). Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • John, P. (2013). Self-locating belief. In N. Feit & A. Capone (Eds.), Attitudes de se. Linguistics, epistemology, metaphysics (pp. 385–408). Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1990). The myth of mental indexicals. Noûs, 24(5), 723–734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13, 3–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2007). Perspectival thought. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2009). De re and de se. In R. Jeshion (Ed.), New essays on singular thought. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2012). Immunity to error through misidentification: What it is and where it comes from. In S. Prosser & F. Recanati (Eds.), Immunity to error through misidentification(pp. 180–201). Cambridge: CUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (2003, June). Unity of consciousness and the self. Meeting of the Aristotelian Society, pp. 325–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (2011). Awareness and identification of self. In L. Jee Loo & P. John (Eds.), Consciousness and the self: New essays (pp. 22–50). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1970). Propositional attitudes De Dicto and De Re. The Journal of Philosophy, 67(21), 883–896.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1995). De Re belief, action explanations and the essential indexical. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong, D. Raffman, & N. Asher (Eds.), Modality, morality and belief (pp. 235–249). Cambridge: CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alessandro Capone .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Capone, A. (2016). Impure ‘de se’ Thoughts and Pragmatics (and How This Is Relevant to Pragmatics and IEM). In: Capone, A., Kiefer, F., Lo Piparo, F. (eds) Indirect Reports and Pragmatics. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 5. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-21395-8_24

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-21395-8_24

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-21394-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-21395-8

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics