Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Argumentation Library ((ARGA,volume 28))

Abstract

This chapter is a slightly revised version of a keynote address at the 2014 International Society for the Study of Argumentation conference. I describe the emergence of two themes that I think are key to the constitution of informal logic. One is the development of analytic tools for the recognition, identification and display of so-called “non-interactive” arguments. The other is the development of evaluative tools for assessing deductive, inductive, and other kinds of arguments (or other evaluative criteria than deductive validity and inductive strength). At the end I mention several current interests of informal logic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    HAT is the successor to FAT, Fundamentals of Argumentation Theory (van Eemeren et al. 1996).

  2. 2.

    “Natural language deductivism” is the thesis that all arguments [in natural languages] should be interpreted as attempts to create deductively valid arguments.

  3. 3.

    On these distinctions see, e.g., Govier (1985), Thomas (1986), Yanal (1991, 2003), Freeman (1993), Ennis (1996), LeBlanc (1998), Fisher (2001), Goddu (2003), Bailin and Battersby (2010), Vaughn and MacDonald (2010), Groarke and Tindale (2013), Hitchcock (2015).

  4. 4.

    The developments described in this and the next paragraph are found in Thomas (1973), Scriven (1976), Johnson and Blair (1977) and Govier (1985), among many others.

  5. 5.

    Some seem to conceptualize better visually, others, numerically. I don’t know whether this difference has occurred to others and been investigated. The current fashion of developing computer-generated tree diagrams might be disadvantaging part of the student population.

  6. 6.

    Among others I would include here Hitchcock (1983), Govier (1987), Biro and Siegel (1992), Johnson (2000), Pinto (2001), Freeman (2005), Allen (2013).

  7. 7.

    Logicians gave their use of ‘validity’ a special, technical sense. In that sense, expressed in one of several possible ways, an inference from a set of premises to a conclusion is “valid” just in case the conclusion could not possibly be false if the premises were true.

  8. 8.

    The terms ‘acceptability,’ ‘relevance’ and ‘sufficiency’ were originally introduced as names for the three criteria for logically good arguments by Johnson and Blair (1977).

References

  • Allen, D. (2013). Trudy Govier and premise adequacy. Informal Logic, 33(2), 116–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailin, S., & Battersby, M. (2010). Reason in the balance: An inquiry approach to critical thinking. Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biro, J., & Siegel, H. (1992). Normativity, argumentation and an epistemic theory of fallacies. In F. H. van Eemeren, et al. (Eds.), Argumentation illuminated (pp. 85–103). Amsterdam: SicSat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, J. A. (2012). Groundwork in the theory of argumentation, Selected papers of J. Anthony Blair. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blair, J. A., & Johnson, R. H. (1987). Argumentation as dialectical. Argumentation, 1(1), 41–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copi, I. M. (1954). Symbolic logic. New York: The Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damer, T. E. (1987). Attacking faulty reasoning (2nd ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ennis, R. H. (1996). Critical thinking. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro, M. A. (1981). Fallacies and the evaluation of reasoning. American Philosophical Quarterly, 18, 13–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro, M. A. (2005). Arguments about arguments, systematic, critical and historical essays in logical theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro, M. A. (2013). Meta-argumentation, an approach to logic and argumentation theory. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, A. (1988). The logic of real arguments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, A. (2001). Critical thinking: An introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fohr, S. D. (1979). The deductive-inductive distinction. Informal Logic Newsletter, 2(2), 5–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fohr, S. D. (1980). Deductive-inductive: Reply to criticisms. Informal Logic Newsletter, 3(1), 5–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, J. B. (1988). Thinking logically: Basic concepts for reasoning. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, J. B. (1993). Thinking logically: Basic concepts for reasoning. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, J. B. (2005). Acceptable premises, an epistemic approach to an informal logic problem. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, J. B. (2011). Evaluating conductive arguments in light of the Toulmin model. In J. A. Blair & R. H. Johnson (Eds.), Conductive argument, an overlooked type of defeasible reasoning (pp. 127–144). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godden, D. (2005). Deductivism as an interpretive strategy, reply to Groarke’s recent defense of reconstructive deductivism. Argumentation and Advocacy, 41, 168–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goddu, G. (2003). Against the ‘ordinary summing’ test for convergence. Informal Logic, 23(3), 215–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. (1979). Critical review of Carl Wellman’s Challenge and response. Informal Logic Newsletter, 2(3), 10–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. (1980a). More on deductive and inductive arguments. Informal Logic Newsletter, 2(3), 7–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. (1980b). Assessing arguments, what range of standards? Informal Logic Newsletter, 3(1), 2–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. (1985). A practical study of argument (1st ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. (1987). Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. (1999). The philosophy of argument. Newport News, VA: Vale Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L. (1995). What pragma-dialectics can learn from deductivism, and what deductivism can learn from pragma-dialectics. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Proceedings of the third ISSA conference on argumentation (Vol. 2, pp. 138–145). Analysis and evaluation Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L. (1999). Deductivism within pragma-dialectics. Argumentation, 13, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L. (2002). Johnson on the metaphysics of argument. Argumentation, 16, 277–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L. (2013). Informal logic. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Spring 2013 Ed. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/logic-informal/.

  • Groarke, L. A., & Tindale, C. W. (2004). Good reasoning matters: A constructive approach to critical thinking (3rd ed.). Don Mills, ON: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C. L. (1970). Fallacies. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, H.V. 2014a. Mill, informal logic and argumentation. In A. Loizides (Ed.), John Stuart Mill’s a system of logic: Critical appraisals (pp. 192–217). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, H. V. (Ed.). (2014b). Riel’s defence: Perspectives on his speeches. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, H. V. (2014c). Narrative and logical order in Riel’s address to the jury. In H. V. Hansen (Ed.), Riel’s defence: Perspectives on his speeches (pp. 135–164). Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2014). Indouctive logic. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Summer 2014 Ed. (forthcoming). http://plato.stanfrd.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/logic-inductive/.

  • Hitchcock, D. (1980). Deductive and inductive: Types of validity, not types of argument. Informal Logic Newsletter, 2(3), 9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, D. (1983). Critical thinking: A guide to evaluating information. Toronto: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, D. (2015). Freeman’s syntactic criterion for linkage. Informal Logic, 35(1), 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, F. (1980). Deductively-inductively. Informal Logic Newsletter, 3(1), 4–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R. H. (1996). The rise of informal logic. Newport News, VA: Vale Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R. H. (2000). Manifest rationality, A pragmatic theory of argument. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R. H., & Blair, J. A. (1977, 1983, 1993). Logical self-defense. Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, H. (1971). Logic and contemporary rhetoric (1st ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • LeBlanc, J. (1998). Thinking clearly: A guide to critical reasoning. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, R. C. (2001). Argument, inference and dialectic, collected papers on informal logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, R. C., Blair, J. A., & Parr, K. E. (1993). Reasoning, a practical guide for Canadian students. Scarborough, ON: Prentice-Hall Canada.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scriven, M. (1976). Reasoning. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seech, Z. (1988). Open minds and everyday reasoning. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, S. N. (1973, 1986). Practical reasoning in natural language (3rd ed. 1986) Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tindale, C. W. (1999). Acts of arguing, a rhetorical model of argument. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tindale, C. W. (2004). Rhetorical argumentation. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, Stephen. (1958). The uses of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tully, R. E. (1995). Logic, informal. In T. Honderich (Ed.), The Oxford companion to philosophy (p. 500). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., et al. (Eds.). (1996). Fundamentals of argumentation theory. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., et al. (Eds.). (2014). Handbook of argumentation theory. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaughn, L., & MacDonald, C. (2010). The power of critical thinking (2nd Canadian ed.). Don Mills, ON: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1992). Plausible argument in everyday conversation. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1995). Informal logic. In R. Audi (Ed.), The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy (p. 376). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1996). Argument schemes for presumptive reasoning. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1998). The new dialectic. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D., Reed, C., & Macagno, F. (2008). Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weddle, P. (1979). Inductive, deductive. Informal Logic Newsletter, 2(1), 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weddle, P. (1980). Good grief! More on induction/deduction. Informal Logic Newsletter, 3(1), 10–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, C. (1971). Challenge and response, justification in ethics. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wisdom, J. (1991). Proof and explanation, The Virginia lectures (ed. by S. F. Barker). Lanham, MD: University Press of America (Originally delivered at the University of Virginia in spring 1957).

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (2013). Errors of reasoning, naturalizing the logic of inference. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yanal, R. J. (1991). Dependent and independent reasons. Informal Logic, 13(3), 137–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yanal, R. J. (2003). Linked and convergent reasons—again. In J. Anthony Blair, et al. (Eds.), Informal logic at 25: Proceedings of the Windsor conference, CD-ROM. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

My thanks to Fellows at the Centre for Research in Reasoning, Argumentation and Rhetoric at the University of Windsor for critical comments on, and suggestions for improvements of, earlier drafts of the keynote address, including Hans Hansen, Catherine Hundleby, Leo Groarke, Marcello Guarini, Bruno Leclercq, Christopher Tindale, and especially Ralph Johnson and Robert Pinto.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. Anthony Blair .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Anthony Blair, J. (2015). What Is Informal Logic?. In: van Eemeren, F., Garssen, B. (eds) Reflections on Theoretical Issues in Argumentation Theory. Argumentation Library, vol 28. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-21103-9_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics