Skip to main content

The Role of Logic in Analyzing and Evaluating Argumentation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 1735 Accesses

Part of the book series: Argumentation Library ((ARGA,volume 27))

Abstract

What is the relationship between logic and argumentation theory? The answer to this question depends, of course, to a large extent on the way in which logic and argumentation theory are conceived and defined. Opting for different concepts of logic and argumentation theory could result in the view that there is no relationship at all, that logic and argumentation theory are the same, that logic is part of argumentation theory, that argumentation theory is part of logic, or that some more complex variant of either of these possibilities prevails. Acknowledging that other choices can be made, I start my attempt to answer the question about the relationship between logic and argumentation theory with a general indication of my understanding of logic and argumentation theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Van Benthem (2009, p. 19) observes that “modern logic just studies some products of […] acts, such as inference forms, or static instantaneous knowledge and beliefs of agents. It does not study those acts themselves, even though only the latter create the products, and make sense of them”.

  2. 2.

    See, in particular, Johnson (2000).

  3. 3.

    It may also be the case that for other reasons it is immediately apparent which premise has been left unexpressed. The communicative activity type in which the argumentation takes place, for instance, might provide the solution. Then logic does not play a part in the reconstruction process.

  4. 4.

    For the rules of communication, which integrate Gricean maxims and speech act conditions, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992, pp. 49–55).

  5. 5.

    The heuristic starting point of the pragma-dialectical procedure for making unexpressed premises explicit consists in reconstructing the reasoning underlying the argumentation as a logically valid argument, whose conclusion cannot be false if the premises are true. In practice, it is not always fully clear whether the argument should indeed be validated. The speaker may, after all, have argued in an invalid way. Unless there are good reasons for not doing so, it is for reason’s sake nevertheless pragma-dialectical policy to follow the procedure.

  6. 6.

    I am not certain that it is up to argumentation theorists to give a specific and definitive answer to the general question of exactly what kind of logical validity criterion is to be preferred.

  7. 7.

    For these empirical sources, see van Eemeren (2010, pp. 16–19), who distinguishes between the text, the micro, meso, macro and textual contexts, logical and pragmatic inferences, and general and specific background information.

  8. 8.

    For a summary of the general procedure to determine the pragmatic optimum, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992, pp. 64–68, pp. 142–144).

  9. 9.

    A Constructive Dilemma neither has two premises nor can it be easily reconstructed as an argument with two premises.

  10. 10.

    Each of our rules for critical discussion makes it possible to satisfy a necessary condition for the resolution of a difference of opinion. As a whole, the rules are conducive to the resolution of a difference of opinion by means of argumentative discussions.

  11. 11.

    In certain cases, as in argumentation by analogy, the soundness of the reasoning involved in the argumentation does not play a prominent part in the process of convincing the antagonist, so that logic is not pertinent to the assessment of the use of the argument scheme employed.

  12. 12.

    See van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992, pp. 92–102).

  13. 13.

    See van Eemeren, Garssen and Meuffels for a report of experimental empirical research into the agreement between the pragma-dialectical code of conduct for reasonable discussions and the argumenative position adopted by the parties. See also Mohammed (2009) and Andone (2010).

References

  • Andone, C. (2010). Maneuvering strategically in a political interview. Analyzing and evaluating responses to an accusation of inconsistency. Amsterdam: Rozenberg/Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. (1987). Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R. (2000). Manifest rationality. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R., & Blair, J. A. (1994). Logical self-defence. New York: McGraw-Hill. (1st ed. 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohammed, D. (2009). The Honourable Gentleman should make up his mind. Strategic manoeuvring with accusations of inconsistency in Prime Minister’s Question Time. Unpublished doctoral dissertation University of Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J. (2009). One logician’s perspective on argumentation. Cogency, 1(2), 13–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (2010). Strategic maneuverting in argumentative discourse. Extending the pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Garssen, B., Haaften, T. van, Krabbe, E. C. W., Snoeck Henkemans, A. F., & Wagemans, J. H. M. (2012). Handbook of argumentation theory. An overview of classical and neo-classical perspectictives on argumentation and modern theoretical approaches to argumentative discourse. Dordrecht: Springer. (to be published).

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1984). Speech acts in argumentative discussions. A theoretical model for the analysis of discussions directed towards solving conflicts of opinion. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1992). Argumentation, communication, and fallacies. A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2004). A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Snoeck Henkemans, A. F., with Blair, J. A., Johnson, R. H., Krabbe, E. C. W., Plantin, Ch., Walton, D. N., Willard, Ch. A., Woods, J., & Zarefsky, D. (1996). Fundamentals of argumentation theory: Handbook of historical backgrounds and contemporary developments. Mahwah N. J.: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frans H. van Eemeren .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

van Eemeren, F.H. (2015). The Role of Logic in Analyzing and Evaluating Argumentation. In: Reasonableness and Effectiveness in Argumentative Discourse. Argumentation Library, vol 27. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-20955-5_35

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics