Skip to main content

A Procedural View of Critical Reasonableness

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Reasonableness and Effectiveness in Argumentative Discourse

Part of the book series: Argumentation Library ((ARGA,volume 27))

  • 1726 Accesses

Abstract

When in the study of argumentation we are talking about ‘reasonableness,’ we are discussing the philosophical rationale for adopting a certain theoretical approach to argumentation. Such a rationale may, in our view, be supposed to have two complementary dimensions. First, there is the dimension of ‘problem validity,’ a criterion having to do with the effectiveness of an approach, which has become the single touchstone in the logical perspective on argumentation. Second, there is the dimension of ‘intersubjective validity,’ also referred to as ‘conventional validity,’ a criterion that pertains to the acceptability of an approach to real arguers and features in the rhetorical perspective on argumentation. In modern and postmodern philosophies of argumentation the balance between problem validity and intersubjective validity has been lost. As a consequence, the scale has either tipped toward the logical perspective or toward the rhetorical perspective. In this paper, we propose how the balance can be redressed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It is important to realize that it depends also on the definition of the problem whether or not a certain approach is effective in solving the problem. In our conception, argumentation is aimed at resolving a difference of opinion and the most effective approach to argumentation is the one that serves this purpose best.

  2. 2.

    Taking Albert’s (1985) warning against any form of “revelation model” of the truth to heart, we believe it necessary to keep all justificationism inherent in the geometrical and anthropological conceptions of reasonableness at a firm distance.

  3. 3.

    A great many philosophers make a fundamental distinction between factual judgements and value judgments and are of the opinion that the latter cannot be subjected to a reasonable discussion, because they are based only on subjective preferences. We fear that restricting the bounds of reason to discussions on factual judgments would give a free hand to those, in politics or elsewhere, who do not really care about reasonableness. We agree with Albert (1985) that any topic on which a regulated discussion can be carried out can be dealt with reasonably.

  4. 4.

    According to our principle of externalization, only those challenges need to be dealt with by the protagonist that are somehow advanced in the discussion, whether explicitly, implicitly or indirectly.

  5. 5.

    There are some restrictions, however. Maintaining the burden of proof does not make sense if earlier the protagonist has defended his standpoint already successfully against the same antagonist starting from the same point of departure. It is also a waste of time to start a critical discussion if no joint point of departure can be established.

  6. 6.

    Barth and Krabbe (1982) take a similar approach.

  7. 7.

    Although adopting a presumption clearly prejudges an issue, such an adoption may in Ullman-Margalit’s view be seen as rational in a twofold sense: in any particular instance the presumption is open to rebuttal, and the bias it promotes is independently justifiable. In pragma-dialectical terms, the former would mean that a starting point can be revoked; this, however, is only allowed when it can be shown by offering counter-evidence that this starting point is, after all, not acceptable. The latter would mean that institutional or other contextual support must be available.

  8. 8.

    In his system for dealing with (mixed) disputes, Hamblin (1970, 274) also replaces the concept of burden of proof by the “somewhat simpler concept of initiative”.

  9. 9.

    They have, in fact, the same function as the formal dialectical ‘concessions,’ but in a critical discussion ‘concessions’ are made by both parties.

  10. 10.

    Our contextual commitments are akin to Walton and Krabbe’s (1995) “veiled” or dark-side commitments, albeit that the latter are associated with non-externalized states of mind and are not related with speech acts (cf. Mackenzie and Staines 1999).

  11. 11.

    The fact that minimization of disagreement, rather than maximization of agreement, is aimed for is, as a matter of fact, a good illustration of how critical rationalist insight and utilitarian pragmatic insight conjoin. A system of argumentation rules which encourages discussants to pronounce their doubts and to work out how far the disagreements ensuing from such expressions of doubt can be resolved, is in our view preferable to a system of argumentation rules which seeks to ensure agreement.

References

  • Albert, H. (1985). Treatise on critical reason. (Rorty, M. V. (1967). Traktat über kritische Vernunft. Tübingen: Mohr, Trans.) Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barth, E. M., & Krabbe, E. C. W. (1982). From axiom to dialogue: A philosophical study of logics and argumentation. Berlin/New York: Walter de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1984). Speech acts in argumentative discussions: A theoretical model for the analysis of discussions directed towards solving conflicts of opinion. Berlin/New York: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1992). Argumentation, communication, and fallacies: A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2002). Critical discussion. University Park, PA: Penn State Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Houtlosser, P. (1999). Strategic manoeuvring in argumentative discourse. In Discourse Studies, 1, 479–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C. L. (1970). Fallacies. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamlah, W., & Lorenzen, P. (1984). Logical propaedeutic: Pre-school of reasonable discourse. (Hoke, R. (1967). Logische Propädeutik; Vorschule des vernünftigen Redens. Mannheim: Hochschultaschenbücher-Verlag, Trans.) Lanham, MD: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie, J., & Staines, Ph. (1999). Hamblin’s case for commitment: A reply to Johnson. Philosophy & Rhetoric, 32, 14–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1977). Dialectics: A controversy-oriented approach to the theory of knowledge. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. E. (1976). Knowing and acting. An invitation to philosophy. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. E. (2001). Return to reason. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ullmann-Margalit, E. (1983). On presumption. Journal of Philosophy, 80, 143–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1988). Burden of proof. Argumentation, 2, 233–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N., & Krabbe, E. C. W. (1995). Commitment in dialogue: Basic concepts of interpersonal reasoning. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whately, R. (1846). Elements of rhetoric: Comprising an analysis of the laws of moral evidence and of persuasion, with rules for argumentative composition and elocution. Facs. Ed. Douglas Ehninger 1963. London/Amsterdam: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frans H. van Eemeren .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

van Eemeren, F.H., Houtlosser, P. (2015). A Procedural View of Critical Reasonableness. In: Reasonableness and Effectiveness in Argumentative Discourse. Argumentation Library, vol 27. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-20955-5_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics