Skip to main content

Collingwood’s Claim that History is a Science

  • Chapter
Studies on Collingwood, History and Civilization
  • 237 Accesses

Abstract

Though Collingwood emphatically declared that history is a science, this claim has hardly been taken seriously by Collingwood scholars, primarily because Collingwood has never worked it out properly. Collingwood’s claim concerning the scientific nature of history is based on his view that it is inferential, though in a specific way, that is, being neither inductive nor deductive. He has never explained the nature of the specific type of inference involved, however. It is argued that this third way of inference as conceived by Collingwood corresponds to the theory of abductive reasoning as developed by Charles Peirce, initially called by him hypothetical reasoning. Afterwards, Peirce changed the syllogistic form in which he initially framed his theory of hypothetical inference into a theory in which hypothesis, deduction, and induction are conceived as three stages in scientific inquiry, using the term ‘abduction’ instead of hypothetical inference. In his Autobiography Collingwood gives two examples of this type of reasoning, corresponding to Peirce’s conception of scientific reasoning. In The Principles of History, however, Collingwood develops a too limited conception of historical inference. The chapter ends with considering the views of J. Hintikka on Peirce’s theory of abduction. He conceives this theory as exhibiting particular strategic rules, in which interrogation plays a prominent part. This view accords well with Collingwood’s logic of question and answer, Hintikka indeed referring to him. Considering the argument developed in this chapter, Collingwood’s claim that history is a science is after all noticeably supported.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    R.G. Collingwood. The Principles of History and Other Writings in Philosophy of History, W.H. Dray and W.J. van der Dussen eds. (Oxford, 1999) will be abbreviated in the text as PH.

  2. 2.

    G. D’Oro, ‘Collingwood on Re-enactment and the Identity of Thought’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (2000), 87–101.

  3. 3.

    Ibid., 87.

  4. 4.

    G. Frege, ‘On Sinn and Bedeutung’ (1892) and ‘Thought’ (1918), in: M. Beany ed., The Frege Reader (Oxford, 1997), 151–171, 325–345. For a discussion of the relevance of Frege’s theories for the re-enactment doctrine, see Chap. 4, ‘The Philosophical Context of Collingwood’s Re-enactment Theory’.

  5. 5.

    R.G. Collingwood, The Idea of History (Oxford, 1946); revis. ed., Jan van der Dussen ed. (Oxford, 1993) will be abbreviated in the text as IH.

  6. 6.

    This idea is worked out by Collingwood in the paragraph λόγῳ χρόνῳ πρότερον (‘prior in logic, in time’) in his ‘Notes Towards a Metaphysic’, concluding that ‘history is the deployment of a concept in a process that is at once logical and temporal’ (PH, 122).

  7. 7.

    Karl R. Popper, ‘Of Clouds and Clocks’, in: idem, Objective Knowledge. An Evolutionary Approach (Oxford, 1972), 206–255, there 212.

  8. 8.

    Karl R. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery (New York, 1959), 31.

  9. 9.

    The Essential Peirce. Selected Philosophical Writings, vol. 1 (1867–1893), Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel eds. (Bloomington and Indianapolis, 1992), 186–99.

  10. 10.

    Ibid., 188.

  11. 11.

    Ibid., 189.

  12. 12.

    Ibid., 197.

  13. 13.

    Ibid., 194.

  14. 14.

    Ibid., 189, 198.

  15. 15.

    Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. i–vi, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss eds. (Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935), 6.606.

  16. 16.

    Ibid.

  17. 17.

    Ibid., 2.74.

  18. 18.

    W.H. Dray, History as Re-enactment. R.G. Collingwood’s Idea of History (Oxford, 1995), 42.

  19. 19.

    The Essential Peirce. Selected Philosophical Writings, vol. 2 (1893–1913), Nathan Houser a.o. eds. (Bloomington and Indianapolis, 1998), 231.

  20. 20.

    See K.T. Fann, Peirce’s Theory of Abduction (The Hague, 1970), 28–35.

  21. 21.

    The Essential Peirce, vol. 2, Houser a.o. eds., 75–114.

  22. 22.

    Ibid., 94–5.

  23. 23.

    Ibid., 95.

  24. 24.

    Ibid., 97.

  25. 25.

    Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Hartshorne and Weiss eds., 6.524, 6.528.

  26. 26.

    Ibid., 6.524.

  27. 27.

    Ibid., 5.168.

  28. 28.

    Collingwood extensively discusses the issue of the chain of towers in ‘Roman Signal-Stations on the Cumberland Coast’, Transactions of the Cumberland and Westmorland Antiquarian and Archaeological Society, New Series 29 (1929), 138–65. See also Jan van der Dussen, History as a Science. The Philosophy of R.G. Collingwood (Dordrecht, 2012), 221.

  29. 29.

    The Essential Peirce, vol. 2, Houser a.o. eds., 13.

  30. 30.

    Ibid., 14.

  31. 31.

    D. Walton, Abductive Reasoning (Tuscaloosa, 2004), 42.

  32. 32.

    Ibid., 245.

  33. 33.

    R.G. Collingwood, The Archaeology of Roman Britain (London, 1930).

  34. 34.

    R.G. Collingwood, The Principles of Art (Oxford, 1938), 251.

  35. 35.

    Th.A. Sebeok, ‘You Know My Method’. A Juxtaposition of Charles S. Peirce and Sherlock Holmes (Bloomington, 1980); U. Eco and Th.A. Sebeok eds., The Sign of Three. Dupin, Holmes, Peirce (Bloomington and Indianapolis, 1988).

  36. 36.

    Walton, Abductive Reasoning, 226–7.

  37. 37.

    The Essential Peirce, vol. 2, Houser a.o. eds., 231.

  38. 38.

    Walton, Abductive Reasoning, 134.

  39. 39.

    D. Walton, Argument Structure. A Pragmatic Theory (Toronto, 1996), 263.

  40. 40.

    See P.A. Flach and A.C. Kakas eds., Abduction and Induction. Essays on their Relation and Integration (Dordrecht, 2000).

  41. 41.

    N.R. Hanson, Patterns of Discovery. An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science (Cambridge, 1965), 73–85.

  42. 42.

    J. Hintikka, ‘What is Abduction? The Fundamental Problem of Contemporary Epistemology’, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 34, nr. 3 (1998), 503–33, there 506.

  43. 43.

    Ibid., 512–13.

  44. 44.

    Ibid., 519.

  45. 45.

    Ibid.

  46. 46.

    Ibid., 523.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

van der Dussen, J. (2016). Collingwood’s Claim that History is a Science. In: Studies on Collingwood, History and Civilization. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-20672-1_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics