Skip to main content

Rationality and Collective Beliefs

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Cognitive Autonomy and Methodological Individualism

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 22))

  • 738 Accesses

Abstract

As well as being accused of being committed to reductionism, methodological individualism has been criticized because it has been considered to be tantamount to a utilitarian theory of action. According to utilitarianism (and specifically according to the most recent version of it, namely the rational choice model), action is always based on instrumental rationality and on the attempt to maximize subjective utility on the basis of expected consequences (see Demeulenaere 1996, 2003; Boudon 2001, p. 42; Oliverio 2007, pp. 27 ff.). Because methodological individualism is confused with utilitarianism, it has been criticized on the grounds that many actions cannot be explained in utilitarian terms, and that utilitarianism is unable to decipher a great number of relevant social phenomena. However, the equivalence between methodological individualism and utilitarianism does not hold. While it is true that some methodological individualists endorse a utilitarian theory of action (e.g. Becker 1976), other advocates of this approach, such as Hayek, do not. The individualist tradition is informed by a wealth of perspectives. Because of the impossibility of explaining all human beliefs in utilitarian terms, the tendency to regard methodological individualism as being based on utilitarianism paves the way to an objectivistic approach to social research. It legitimates the idea that many collective beliefs can only be explained in holistic terms, i.e. as the products of a socio-cultural determinism.

This chapter draws on my chapter “Hayek’s Connectionist Psychology as a Defense for the Sociology of Good Reasons”. In Cherkaoui M and Hamilton P. eds. Raymond Boudon. A life in Sociology. Essays in Honour of Raymond Boudon, Vol. 2, Oxford: The Bardewell Press, 2009.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It must be noted that Boudon (1995, pp. 558–563) does not consider rationality as an ontological attribute of action. For him, it is only an epistemological presupposition which must be followed by studying social phenomena. This means that Boudon does not rule out the possibility that a sociologist, having investigated an action, can conclude that it is irrational because it is not the product of “good reasons” (see also Bronner 2003, p. 28).

  2. 2.

    Contradicting his own criticism of Hayek, Boudon (1994, p. 61) partly acknowledged that an analogy exists between Hayek’s theory of the meta-conscious framework of cognition and Simmel’s theory of the a priori categories.

  3. 3.

    As Di Nuoscio (2009, p. 186) remarked, Mises’ praxeology “can endow the Popperian logic of the situation with a sound logical basis”. According to Popper (1994), every action is based on the schema of “problems–theories–criticisms”. Consequently, Popper argues that understanding an action requires the reconstruction of the way in which the actor perceives the existence of the problem to be solved. The actor develops a sort of conjecture regarding his/her situation as well what he or she considers to be the best means to solve the perceived problem. This conjecture is what Popper calls the logic of the situation (see Jarvie 1972, pp. 3-36). In Popper’s opinion, the social scientist must develop an empirically testable meta-conjecture about the agent’s conjecture by reconstructing the agent’s interpretative horizon. The social scientist also has to explain whether the way in which the actor perceives the situation matches the objective situation. This is useful in explaining actions that do not achieve the expected goal. In fact, according to Di Nuoscio (2009), Mises provides a good foundation for Popper’s theory of the logic of the situation because, conceiving the rationality principle as a tautological property of action, he assigns “a sort of epistemological immunity” to this principle. As will be pointed out in Chap. 6, Popper failed to provide a satisfactory definition of the rationality principle (see also Leeson and Boettke 2006, pp. 15–20).

References

  • Becker, G.S. 1976. The economic approach to human behavior. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. 1994. The art of self-persuasion. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. 1995. Le juste et le vrai. Paris: Fayard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. 2000. Études sur les sociologies classiques II. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. 2001. The origins of value. Piscataway, NJ:/London: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. 2003. Raison, bonnes raisons. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. 2005. The poverty of relativism. Oxford: The Bardwell Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. 2007. Essais sur la théorie générale de la rationalité. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. 2009. La rationalité. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R., and F. Bourricaud. 1990. A critical dictionary of sociology. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouvier, A. 1999. Philosophie des sciences sociales. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bronner, G. 2003. L’empire des croyances. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bronner, G. 2006. Vie et Mort des croyances collectives. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bronner, G. 2007. L’empire de l’erreur: Eléments de sociologie cognitive. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bronner, G. 2009. La pensée extrême. Paris: Denoël.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bronner, G. 2011. The future of collective beliefs. Oxford: The Bardwell Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cubeddu, R. 1995. Friedrich A. Von Hayek. Quaderni del Centro di Metodologia delle scienze sociali, Luiss. Roma: Borla.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demeulenaere, P. 2003. Les normes sociales: Entre accords et désaccords. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demeulenaere, P. 2012. De l’individualisme méthodologique à la sociologie analytique. In La théorie sociale contemporaine, ed. Keuvheyan, R. and G. Bronner. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Iorio, F. 2009. Hayek’s connectionist psychology as a defense for the sociology of good reasons. In Raymond Boudon. A life in sociology. Essays in honour of Raymond Boudon, ed. Cherkaoui M, and P. Hamilton, Vol. 2. Oxford: The Bardewell Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Iorio, F., and E. Di Nuoscio. 2014. Rethinking Boudon’s cognitive rationality in the light of Mises’ apriorism and Gadamer’s hermeneutics. Journal des Économistes et des Études Humaines, Pre-published online: ISSN (Online) 2153-1552, ISSN (Print) 2194-5799. doi:10.1515/jeeh-2014-0010, December 2014.

  • Di Nuoscio, E. 2000. Epistemologia dell’azione e ordine spontaneo. Evoluzionismo e individualismo metodologico in Herbert Spencer. Soveria Mannelli: Rubbettino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Nuoscio, E. 2006. Il mestiere dello scienziato sociale: Un’introduzione all’epistemologia delle scienze sociali. Naples: Liguori.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Nuoscio, E. 2009. The rationality of human action: Towards a Mises–Popper–Boudon Model?. In Raymond Boudon: A life in sociology—Essays in honour of Raymond Boudon, ed. Cherkaoui M., and P. Hamilton, Vols. 4. Oxford: The Bardwell Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Nuoscio, E. 2011. Epistemologia del dialogo: Una difesa filosofica del confronto pacifico tra culture. Rome: Carrocci.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H.L., and S.E. Dreyfus. 2000. Mind over machine. The power of human intuition and expertise in the era of the computer. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupuy, J.-P. 1990. Ordres et désordres. Enquête sur un nouveau paradigme. Paris: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleetwood, S. 1995. Hayek’s political economy: The socio-economics of order. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H.-G. 1981. Reason in the age of science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H.-G. 1997. Philosophical hermeneutics. Berkley/Los Angeles/London: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H.-G. 2006. Truth and method. London/New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. 2008. Rationality for mortals. How people cope with uncertainity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. 1944. The road to Serfdom. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. 1952a. The counter-revolution of science studies on the abuse of reason. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. 1952b. The sensory order: An inquiry into the foundations of theoretical psychology. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. 1973. Law, legislation and liberty, Vol. 1: Rules and order. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. 1978. New studies in philosophy, politics, economics and the history of ideas. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. 1979. Law, legislation and liberty, Vol. 3; The political order of a free people. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. 1990. The fatal conceit. The errors of socialism. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. 1994. Hayek on Hayek: An autobiographical dialog. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heritier, P. 1997. Ordine spontaneo ed evoluzione nel pensiero di Hayek. Naples: Jovene.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jarvie, I. 1972. Concepts and society. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jost, W., and M.J. Hyde (eds.). 1997. Rhetoric and hermeneutics in our time: A reader. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lachmann, L. 2007. The legacy of Max Weber. Auburn, AL: The Ludwig von Mises Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeson, M.T., and P.J. Boettke. 2006. Was Mises right? Review of Social Economy LXIV: 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • McQuade, T.J. 2007. Science and market as adaptive classifying systems. In Cognition and economics: Advances in Austrian economics, Vol. 9, ed. E. Krecke, C. Krecke, and R.M. Kopple. Oxford: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manzo, G. 2013. Is rational choice theory still a rational choice of theory? A response to Opp. Social Science Information 52(3): 361–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marsh, L. 2010a. Ryle and Oakeshott on the know-how/know-that distinction. In The meanings of Michael Oakeshott’s conservatism, ed. C. Abel. Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marsh, L. 2010b. Hayek: Cognitive scientist avant la lettre: Advances”. Advances in Austrian Economics 13: 115–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadeau, R. 2003. Cultural evolution true and false: A debunking of Hayek’s critics. In Proceedings of 7th ESHET Conference, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nemo, P. 1988. La société de droit selon Hayek. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliverio, A. 2007. Strategia della scelta: Introduzione alla teoria della decisione. Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, J. 2009. Per un nuovo Illuminismo. Milan: Bompiani.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, J., J.F. Varela, B. Pachoud, and J.-M. Roy. 1999. Beyond the gap: An introduction to naturalizing phenomenology. In Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science, ed. J. Petitot, J.F. Varela, B. Pachoud, and J.-M. Roy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petroni, A.M. 1991. L’individualisme methodologique. Journal des Economistes et des Études Humaines 2(1), Mars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R. 1994. The myth of the framework: In defence of science and rationality (ed. by M. A. Notturno). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzello, S. 1999. The Economics of mind. Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, V.L. 2008. Rationality in economics. Constructivist and ecological forms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J. 1989a. Connaître les sciences cognitives: Tendances et perspectives. Paris: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J. 1989b. Autonomie et Connaissance. Essai sur le vivant. Paris: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, L. 1998. Human action: A Treatise on economics. Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, L. 2002. The ultimate foundation of economic science. An essay on method. Irvington-on-Hudson, NY: Foundation for Economic Education.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winograd, T., and F. Flores. 1987. Understanding computers and cognition: A new foundation for design. Norwood, NJ: Ablex Corporation.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Francesco Di Iorio .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Di Iorio, F. (2015). Rationality and Collective Beliefs. In: Cognitive Autonomy and Methodological Individualism. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 22. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-19512-4_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics