Skip to main content

Bernard de Mandeville and the Shaping of Conjectural History

  • Chapter
Bernard de Mandeville's Tropology of Paradoxes

Part of the book series: Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ((AUST,volume 40))

Abstract

This paper argues that Bernard Mandeville’s Fable of the Bees, Part II (1729), is the first work to bring together all the elements of conjectural history, a form that rose to prominence in the Enlightenment, between 1750 and 1800. Conjectural history builds on the natural law tradition of Hobbes and Locke, but it is non-contractual and considers a longer span of history. In both these respects, Pufendorf’s account of early society opens a way that is taken by later conjectural historians. Of these, Mandeville’s Fable, Part II, is the earliest to present a naturalistic, non-contractual narrative of the early stages of civil society. Although Vico’s New Science exhibits some of these features, it remains tied to a providential and cyclical view of history.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I am not aware of evidence that either Vico or Mandeville influenced the other’s thought or use of form.

  2. 2.

    Istvan Hont traced the way that Pufendorf’s revisions of Hobbes’s state of nature – incorporating commerce in the earliest stage, and distinguishing between the founding of society and of the state – prepared the way for the stadial narratives of the Scottish Enlightenment (Hont 2005). I do not conceive of conjectural history as being limited to accounts that specify exactly four stages based on means of subsistence; this conception of the genre as “four-stage theory” owes much to Meek 1976. On the theological underpinnings of Pufendorf’s natural jurisprudence and its role in histories of early society in the Scottish Enlightenment, see Moore and Silverthorne 1983.

  3. 3.

    In support of this picture of earliest man, Pufendorf cites Lucretius, On the Nature of Things, Bk. 5, and refers as well to the similar account of Diodorus Siculus, Bk. 1, ch. 5. Wiktor Stoczkowski provocatively argues that later conjectural, evolutionary, and anthropological accounts of the earliest human societies and their stages of development almost all conform to the paradigms established by traditional or common-sense anthropology, often traceable to ancient writers (Stoczkowski 2002).

  4. 4.

    Pufendorf thus maintains a thesis that has only recently regained currency, as a result of work in contemporary evolutionary biology – that humans more often benefit from being honest and loyal than from cheating and lying (Pufendorf 1717: 145; 4.4.2). See de Waal 1996.

  5. 5.

    I am thus in agreement with Mikko Tolonen, who considers Mandeville’s Part II as a conjectural history (Tolonen 2013: 77–99), and discusses Mandeville’s account of the unintended, non-contractual development of society through stages over a lengthy period of time. My emphasis here, however, is on Mandeville as the first thinker to put together these elements of the form we now recognize as conjectural history.

  6. 6.

    Malcolm Jack draws attention to Mandeville’s emphasis on the extreme length of time required for the gradual processes of socialization of early mankind, as well as the relation of Mandeville’s account of early men to the descriptions of tribal people in European travel narratives of the preceding two centuries (Jack 1989: 53–62). Jack’s analysis of Mandeville is particularly valuable for placing the Fable, Part II in relation to a pair of later conjectural histories that see social development as a deeply ambiguous process of both progress and decline – Rousseau’s Discourse on Inequality and Ferguson’s Essay on the History of Civil Society.

  7. 7.

    Martin Otero Knott emphasizes Mandeville’s shift away from “theoretical stories” of social contracts to a “conjecturally speculative . . . history of society” in the Fable, Part II (Knott 2014: 40).

  8. 8.

    J. A. W. Gunn argues that Mandeville does not deny the existence of providence as the ground for the “mysterious realm of origins” or the ultimate answer to the problem of good and evil in the world (Gunn 1975: 117). Even if granted, this is a very attenuated concept of providence, especially as compared with the prominence of the concept in thinkers such as Vico, or, among later conjectural historians, Kames and Herder. E. J. Hundert argues for the naturalistic character of Mandeville’s analysis (Hundert 1994: 84, 113).

  9. 9.

    In this, his practice resembles that of Nietzsche, in the Genealogy of Morals, Essay 1 (1888), a later conjectural history.

  10. 10.

    The early appearance in Vico’s account of the division between the strong and the weak parallels the originary status of this opposition in Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morals, Essay 1.

  11. 11.

    The concept of the cyclopean family is based on the isolated, primitive, cave-dwelling single families of Cyclops, as depicted, for example in the Odyssey. The cyclopean family also figures as the first stage of human society in Henry Maine’s influential history of Roman legal institutions, Ancient Law (1861).

  12. 12.

    Mark Lilla argues that from his earliest works through the final New Science, Vico is committed to a view of history in which providence exercises a directing hand, shaping human nature for beneficial results. On this account, the New Science falls short of providing a naturalistic account of the genesis and course of human societies (Lilla 1993). Leon Pompa characterizes one of Vico’s many cryptic statements about the world of gentile history as a “strange mixture of claims” which asserts that this historical world is created by man but also that it is the work of a superhuman mind that acts for human ends (Pompa 1990: 161). Karl Löwith argues that Vico “never intended to discard revelation” (Löwith 1949: 135), but for Löwith this retention of providence somehow balances perfectly with a history of merely human actors, so that Vico combines theology and philosophy of history in a way that is not matched by any modern historical thinker.

  13. 13.

    James Thomson’s Liberty (1735–1736) provides another instance, nearly contemporaneous with Vico’s, of the idea that societies develop from primitive beginnings through stages to a possible state of luxury and decline, after which the cycle begins again in another country. See Liberty, Part II: Greece, ll. 3–85 and 391–420 (Thomson 1986). Mandeville’s narrative is notable for its avoidance of the Polybian cyclical or helical return from luxury or corruption to a newly primitive state.

References

  • de Waal, Frans. 1996. Good natured: The origins of right and wrong in humans and other animals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunn, J.A.W. 1975. Mandeville and Wither: Individualism and the workings of providence. In Mandeville studies: New explorations in the art and thought of Dr. Bernard Mandeville, ed. Irwin Primer, 98–118. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1981 [1651]. Leviathan. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hont, Istvan. 2005. The language of sociability and commerce: Samuel Pufendorf and the theoretical foundations of “four-stages theory”. In Jealousy of trade: International competition and the nation-state in historical perspective, ed. Istvan Hont, 159–184. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hundert, E.J. 1994. The enlightenment’s Fable: Bernard Mandeville and the discovery of society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jack, Malcolm. 1989. Corruption and progress: The eighteenth-century debate. New York: AMS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knott, Martin Otero. 2014. Mandeville on governability. The Journal of Scottish Philosophy 12: 19–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lilla, Mark. 1993. G. B. Vico: The making of an anti-modern. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1988 [1689]. Two treatises of government, ed. Peter Laslett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwith, Karl. 1949. Meaning in history. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandeville, Bernard. 1988 [1732]. The fable of the bees: Or, private vices, publick benefits, ed. F.B. Kaye, 2 vols. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meek, Ronald. 1976. Social science and the ignoble savage. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, James, and Michael Silverthorne. 1983. Gershom Carmichael and the natural jurisprudence tradition in eighteenth-century Scotland. In Wealth and virtue: The shaping of political economy in the Scottish enlightenment, ed. Istvan Hont and Michael Ignatieff, 73–87. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pompa, Leon. 1990. Human nature and historical knowledge: Hume, Hegel, and Vico. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pufendorf, Samuel. 1717 [1672]. The law of nature and of nations: Eight books, ed. Jean Barbeyrac, trans. Basil Kennett. London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pufendorf, Samuel. 2003 [1691]. The whole duty of man, according to the law of nature. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, Dugald. 1980 [1794]. Account of the life and writings of Adam Smith, LL.D. In Essays on philosophical subjects, ed. W. P. D. Wightman and J. C. Byce, 269–351. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoczkowski, Wiktor. 2002. Explaining human origins: Myth, imagination, and conjecture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, James. 1986 [1735–1736]. Liberty. In The castle of indolence and other poems, ed. James Sambrook. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tolonen, Mikko. 2013. Mandeville and Hume: Anatomists of civil society. Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vico, Giambattista. 1984 [1744]. The new science, trans. Thomas, Goddard Bergin and Max Harold Frisch. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frank Palmeri .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Palmeri, F. (2015). Bernard de Mandeville and the Shaping of Conjectural History. In: Balsemão Pires, E., Braga, J. (eds) Bernard de Mandeville's Tropology of Paradoxes. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol 40. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-19381-6_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics