Skip to main content

Openings into Clinical Ethics

  • Chapter
  • 709 Accesses

Part of the book series: International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine ((LIME,volume 60))

Abstract

I want to pick up where I left off in Chap. 3. In some respects, it is peculiar that, in the face of the resounding backlash against ‘Big Ethics,’ as it was often called in the 1970s, some physicians continued to entertain the notion that philosophers should, and some of them argued must, become “involved” in clinical medicine. Around the same time (early 1980s) as Alan Fleischman was putting his program for residents in place, for instance, the pediatrician Tomas Silber stated his belief that without such actual, regular involvement in clinical affairs, what he termed the “data base” for understanding, much less contending productively with, the moral issues he regarded as inherent to the daily practice of at least pediatric medicine, would be plainly missing. Precisely that “base” is necessary, he argued, for the medical tasks at hand in any clinical situation. Thus, quite understandably, Silber lamented the “absence of these professionals”—that is, philosophers—“from our daily lives,” although, with Siegler, he endorsed the idea that physicians must for their part immerse themselves in philosophy and theology (Silber TJ, Pediatric Ann 10:13–14, 1981).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Jonsen refers to the work of Alfred Schutz as highly significant for this crucial concept. It is, of course, Schutz’s native air (Schutz and Luckmann 1973). In their book on casuistry, Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin present a more detailed methodology (Jonsen and Toulmin 1988, pp. 307–14).

  2. 2.

    This switch from “typification” to “paradigm” obscures precisely what Jonsen otherwise wants to emphasize: the common uncertainties ingredient to such situations as attract his attention—which ‘paradigm’ hardly makes patent.

  3. 3.

    In Jonsen and Toulmin’s study, this point is even clearer. For instance, they state that the “first substantive task [of casuistry] is to agree just which ‘paradigm’ best fits the circumstances in question” (Jonsen and Toulmin 1988, p. 308). By “fit” it is clear they mean “apply,” as is stated explicitly a bit later: “Deciding what type case, or paradigm, best applies in any given circumstance,” even though this is said to be “only the first step…” (pp. 311, 312). My point is merely that it is quite difficult to see much difference between the casuist and the applied ethics models their argument for a difference seems a matter of smoke and mirrors.

References

  • Agich, George J. 1990. A role theoretic look. Social Science and Medicine 30(4): 389–399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Agich, George J. 2005. What kind of doing is clinical ethics? In Special issue on Richard M. Zaner, ed. Osborne P. Wiggins and John Z. Sadler. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 26(1): 7–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1962. Nicomachean Ethics. Trans. M. Ostwald. Indianapolis: The Liberal Arts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bosk, Charles. 1985. The fieldworker as watcher and witness. The Hastings Center Report 15: 10–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, Arthur. 1982. Applying morality to advances in biomedicine: Can and should it be done? In New knowledge in the biomedical sciences, ed. W.B. Bondeson, H.T. Engelhardt, et al. Boston: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, M.J., and S.W.J. Tolle. 1992. Disconnecting a ventilator at the request of a patient who knows he will then die: The doctor’s anguish. Annals of Internal Medicine 117(3): 254–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glover, J.J., et al. 1986. Teaching ethics on rounds: The ethicist as teacher, consultant, and decision-maker. Theoretical Medicine 7: 13–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gorovitz, Samuel. 1982. Doctors’ dilemmas: Moral conflict and medical care. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonsen, Albert J. 1980. Can an ethicist be a consultant? In Frontiers in medical ethics, ed. V. Abernathy. Cambridge, MA: Ballinger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonsen, Albert J. 1986. Casuistry and clinical ethics. Theoretical Medicine 7: 65–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonsen, Albert, and S.J. Toulmin. 1988. The abuse of casuistry. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • La Puma, John. 1987. Consultations in clinical ethics: Issues and questions in 27 cases. Western Journal of Medicine 146(5): 633–637.

    Google Scholar 

  • La Puma, John, and E.R. Priest. 1992. Medical staff privileges for ethics consultants: An institutional model. Quality Review Bulletin 17–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • La Puma, John, and S.E. Toulmin. 1989. Ethics consultants and ethics committees. Archives of Internal Medicine 149: 1109–1112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • La Puma, John, et al. 1988. An ethics consultation service in a teaching hospital. Journal of the American Medical Association 260(6): 808–881.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1981. After virtue. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orlowski, J.P., et al. 2006. Journal of Medical Ethics 32(9): 499–503.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrino, Edmund D. 1979. Humanism and the physician. Knoxville: University of Tennessee Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiedermayer, D.L., John La Puma, and S.H. Miles. 1989. Ethics consultations masking economic dilemmas in patient care. Archives of Internal Medicine 149: 1303–1305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schutz, Alfred, and Thomas Luckmann. I: 1973. Structures of the life-world, 2 vols. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegler, Mark. 1979. Clinical ethics and clinical medicine. Archives of Internal Medicine 139: 914–915.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silber, Tomas J. 1981. Introduction: Bioethics and the pediatrician. Pediatric Annals 10: 13–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, Stephen. 1982. How medicine saved the life of ethics. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 25: 736–750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, R.M. 1981. The context of self: A phenomenological inquiry using medicine as a clue. Athens: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, R.M. 1993a. Voices and time: The venture of clinical ethics. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 18(1): 9–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, R.M. 1993b. If you don’t ask, you won’t know. In Troubled voices, 119–136. Cleveland: The Pilgrim Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, R.M. 1993c. Accidents and time: The urge to be normal. In Troubled voices, 119–136. Cleveland: The Pilgrim Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, R.M. 1994. Phenomenology and the clinical event. In Phenomenology of the cultural disciplines, Contributions to phenomenology, vol. 16, ed. M. Daniel and L.E. Embree, 39–66. Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Zaner, R.M. (2015). Openings into Clinical Ethics. In: A Critical Examination of Ethics in Health Care and Biomedical Research. International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine, vol 60. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-18332-9_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics