Skip to main content

Trading Portfolios: The Stability of Coalition Governments

  • Chapter
The Political Economy of Governance

Part of the book series: Studies in Political Economy ((POEC))

Abstract

In this chapter, we explore the question of how the inclusion of a niche party influences the allocation of ministries in coalition governments. In particular, we ask whether niche parties have an advantage because of higher values that they place on certain ministries that the other parties are less interested in. We provide a model where two parties are dividing a portfolio of three ministries, and compare the stable coalitions formed by two mainstream parties with those formed by a mainstream party and a niche party. The results show that in some cases the niche party is able to form stable coalitions with higher payoffs than the mainstream party. This advantage, however, makes the niche party a less desirable coalition partner because the latter cannot commit not to ask for better payoffs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This is along the lines of Meguid’s (2005) definition of niche parties.

  2. 2.

    See, for example, Browne and Franklin (1973) and Schofield and Laver (1985).

  3. 3.

    For a comparison of Gamson’s hypothesis, Baron and Ferejohn model, and demand competition model in an experimental setting see Frechette et al. (2005).

  4. 4.

    It is trivial to show that any coalition where one of the parties does not get any ministries is not stable.

  5. 5.

    Note that for two-party coalitions the definitions of M 1 stable and M 2 stable will be the same because an objection can be made against only one party.

References

  • Ansolabehere, S., Snyder J. M., Jr., Strauss, A. B., & Ting, M. M. (2005). Voting weights and formateur advantages in the formation of coalition governments. American Journal of Political Science, 49(3), 550–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, R. J., & Maschler, M. (1964). The bargaining set for cooperative games. In M. Dresher, L. S. Shapley, & A. W. Tucker (Eds.), Advances in game theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R. M. (1970). Conflict of interest: A theory of divergent goals with applications to politics. Chicago: Markham Pub. Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron, D. P., & Ferejohn J. A. (1989) Bargaining in legislatures. American Political Science Review, 83(4), 1181–1206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bassi, A. (2013). A model of endogeneous government formation. American Journal of Political Science, 57(4), 777–793.

    Google Scholar 

  • Browne, E. C., & Franklin, M. N. (1973). Aspects of coalition payoffs in European parliamentary democracies. The American Political Science Review, 67(2):453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frechette, G. R., Kagel, J. H., & Morelli, M. (2005). Gamson’s law versus non-cooperative bargaining theory. Games and Economic Behavior, 51, 365–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gamson, W. A. (1961). A theory of coalition formation. American Sociological Review, 26(3), 373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groseclose, T., & Snyder, J. M. (1996). Buying supermajorities. The American Political Science Review, 90(2), 303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laver, M., & Shepsle, K. A. (1996). Making and breaking governments: Cabinets and legislatures in parliamentary democracies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, L. W., & Vanberg, G. (2003). Wasting time? The impact of ideology and size on delay in coalition formation. British Journal of Political Science, 33(02), 323–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, L. W., & Stevenson, R. T. (2001). Government formation in parliamentary democracies. American Journal of Political Science, 45(1), 33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meguid, B. M. (2005). Competition between unequals: The role of mainstream party strategy in niche party success. American Political Science Review, 99(3), 347–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morelli, M. (1999). Demand competition and policy compromise in legislative bargaining. American Political Science Review, 93(4), 809–820.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peleg, B. (1963). Existence theorem for the bargaining set M 1. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 69(1), 109–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1962). The theory of political coalitions. Yale: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, N. (1978). Generalised bargaining sets for cooperative games. International Journal of Game Theory, 7(3/4), 183–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, N. (1980). The bargaining set in voting games. Behavioral Science, 25(2):120–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, N., & Laver, M. (1985). Bargaining theory and portfolio payoffs in European coalition governments 1945–83. British Journal of Political Science, 15(02), 143–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, J. M., Jr., Ting, M. M., & Ansolabehere, S. (2005). Legislative bargaining under weighted voting. American Economic Review, 95(4), 981–1004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verzichelli, L. (2008). Portfolio allocation. In K. Strøm, W. C. Müller, & B. Torbjörn (Eds.), Cabinets and coalition bargaining: The democractic life cycle in Western Europe (pp. 237–269). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Volden, C., & Carrubba, C. J. (2004). The formation of oversized coalitions in parliamentary democracies. American Journal of Political Science, 48(3), 521–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warwick, P. V., & Druckman, J. N. (2001). Portfolio salience and the proportionality of payoffs in coalition governments. British Journal of Political Science, 31(04), 627–649.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warwick, P. V., & Druckman, J. N. (2006). The portfolio allocation paradox: An investigation into the nature of a very strong but puzzling relationship. European Journal of Political Research, 45(4), 635–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Norman Schofield .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Proposition 1

Consider the coalition ABB. To any objection that Party A can make, Party B can respond by making the same offer to Party C, and vice versa. Consider the coalition ABA. Party B can object with BCC against which Party A does not have any counter objection. Consider the coalition AAB. Party B can object with CBC against which Party A does not have any counter objection. The cases for coalitions BAA, BAB, and BBA are symmetrical.

Proof of Proposition 2

The proof for the stable coalitions formed by parties A and B is the same as the proof for Proposition 1.

For the stable coalitions formed by parties A and C:

  1. 1.

    [(a)]

  2. 2.

    Consider the coalition ACC. To any objection that Party A can make, Party C can respond by the counter objection BCC. To any objection that Party C can make, Party A can respond by making the same offer to Party B.

  3. 3.

    Consider the coalition CAA. To any objection that Party A can make, Party B can respond by the counter objection CBB. To any objection by Party C, where Party C gets two ministries, Party A can respond by making the same offer to Party B. If x < y, however, Party C can also object with coalition BCB against which Party A has no counter objection. Similarly, if z < y, party C can object with coalition BBC against which Party A has no counter objection.

  4. 4.

    Consider the coalition CAC. To any objection that Party C can make, Party A can respond by making the same offer to Party B. If Party A objects with ABB, Party C can respond by the counter objection BCC; however, for this counter objection to be possible we should have a ≥ b + c and y ≥ x. Alternatively, Party C can respond by the counter objection BCB if y ≥ x + z. If Party A objects with BAA, Party C can respond by the counter objection BCC. However, for this counter objection to be valid, we should have y > x, which is an easier condition than the ones listed in the Proposition. Finally, if Party A objects with ABA or AAB, Party C can respond by the counter objection CBC.

  5. 5.

    Consider the coalition CCA. To any objection that Party C can make, Party A can respond with the counter objection BBA. If Party A objects with BAB, Party C can respond by the counter objection BBC; however, for this counter objection to be possible we should have z ≥ x + y. The conditions for responding to other possible objections by Party A are easier to satisfy. Party C can respond to objection ABB with BBC if z ≥ x + y or with BCC if a ≥ b + c or z ≥ x. It can respond to objections ABA with BCC if z ≥ x. Finally, it can respond to objection AAB with counter objection CCB.

  6. 6.

    Consider the coalitions ACA and AAC. Party C can object with BCC against which Party A cannot have any counter objection.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Demirkaya, B., Schofield, N. (2015). Trading Portfolios: The Stability of Coalition Governments. In: Schofield, N., Caballero, G. (eds) The Political Economy of Governance. Studies in Political Economy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-15551-7_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics