Skip to main content

Choosing Appropriate Paradigmatic Examples for Understanding Collective Agency

  • Chapter
Collective Agency and Cooperation in Natural and Artificial Systems

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 122))

Abstract

Recent philosophical discussion of collective agency (CA) pays special attention to small-scale cases of cooperating agents: two persons going for a walk together, preparing a sauce hollandaise together, painting a house together, etc. The underlying assumption behind this focus is that a general concept of CA (which would also include large-scale cases) can and should be derived from such small-scale cases. In this paper, I argue that the choice of small-scale cooperation as a paradigmatic example of CA is problematic. It tends to make us overlook important features, which have to be taken into account when theorizing about CA in general. I develop this line of thought by critically examining the approach taken by Margaret Gilbert and also that of Scott Shapiro, who applies Michael Bratman’s account of CA to cases of what he calls ‘massively shared agency’.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I will try to elucidate what a ‘relevant sense’ of the term ‘group’ could be later within this paper.

  2. 2.

    Sigmund Freud claims that we have to study the processes of interpersonal identification if we want to understand the mechanisms which underlie group formation. See Freud 1949, 70.

  3. 3.

    See Butterfill (in this volume) for such a proposal. What Butterfill is hinting at in this context seems to me to be similar to a mechanism which the phenomenologist Hermann Schmitz calls ‘Einleibung’ (encoporation); a kind of bodily empathy or unreflective motor representation of others, which Schmitz takes to be constitutive for social interaction in general and CA in particular (Schmitz 1994).

  4. 4.

    I would claim that this is so because in the case of a couple the shared goal (if there is one) cannot significantly differ from what the persons constituting the couple want to do. This may be a gradual difference, however, I think it is still significant enough to differentiate between couples and groups.

  5. 5.

    However, we might well imagine a team (within a company for example, which is defined by a specific goal) composed of two individuals that is in some way indifferent towards the exchange of its members, but I claim that this case is significantly different from Gilbert standard example of two people going for a walk together.

  6. 6.

    Raz, like Gilbert, tries to address the question in what way members of a given community are obliged to follow its rules. The point I want to express here, however, is that the “sense of belonging” does not necessarily involve a kind of commitment or obligation.

  7. 7.

    I try to describe the way CA is shaped within social networks like Facebook and Twitter in Poljanšek (2014b).

  8. 8.

    For further considerations concerning the importance of interfaces and the way they shape our everyday lives and social interactions see Poljanšek 2014a.

  9. 9.

    Barry Smith recently argued that we have to take into account the role documents (like, for example, a musical score of an orchestra) play as mesh-creating mechanisms in cases of massively shared agency (Smith 2013). I think this role of documents as ‘mesh-creating’ mechanisms is even more significant in cases of long-term CA. Think just of the ongoing progress within the scientific community: Without documents laying the ground for ongoing research by comprising and stabilizing data it would be hard to imagine how it could take place at all. Here it would be especially important to take into account different kinds of ‘mesh-creating’ mechanism that enable cases of massively shared agency and long-term cases of CA. Again, I’m not able to elaborate these thoughts within this paper.

References

  • Bentley, Arthur. 1908. The process of government. A study of social pressures. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, Michael. 2010. Agency, time and sociality. Proceedings and Addresses of the APA 84(2): 7–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, Michael. 2014. Shared agency. A planning theory of acting together. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cacioppo, John T., and William Patrick. 2008. Loneliness. Human nature and the need for social connection. New York/London: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, Gabriella. 2010. Anonymous – From the Lulz to collective action. New Significance. From http://www.thenewsignificance.com/2011/05/09/gabriella-coleman-anonymous-from-thelulz-to-collective-action/ Accessed 12 May 2014.

  • Freud, Sigmund. 1949. Group psychology and the analysis of the ego. Authorized Translation by James Strachey. London: The Hogarth Press Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, Margaret. 1996. Walking together: A paradigmatic social situation. In Living together. Rationality, sociality and obligation, ed. Gilbert Margaret, 177–194. Lanham: The Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, Margaret. 2006. A theory of political obligation. Membership, commitment and the bonds of society. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas. 1962. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, Christian, and Philip Pettit. 2011. Group agency. The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Materman, Margaret. 1974. Die Natur eines Paradigmas. In Kritik und Erkenntnisfortschritt, ed. Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, 59–88. Braunschweig: Vieweg.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McDougall, William. 1927. The group mind. A sketch of the principles of collective psychology with some attempt to apply them to the interpretation of national life and character. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, Catherine J., E. Elinor Chen, et al. 2004. The interaction of social and emotional processes in the brain. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 16: 1818–1829.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, Mancur. 1968. Die Logik des kollektiven Handelns. Kollektivgüter und die Theorie der Gruppe. Tübingen: Mohr (Siebeck).

    Google Scholar 

  • Poljanšek, Tom. 2014a. Benutzeroberflächen: Techniken der Verhüllung des Technischen. In Haut und Hülle. Umschlag und Verpackung. Techniken des Umschließens und Verkleidens, ed. Ute Seiderer and Michael Fisch, 102–117. Berlin: Rotbuch.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poljanšek, Tom. 2014b. Kritisieren heißt Filtrieren. Eine Kritik kritischer Praxis in sozialen Netzwerken. Juridikum. Zeitschrift für Kritik – Recht – Gesellschaft. Schwerpunkt “Internet und Freiheit” 4/2014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1984. The obligation to obey: Revision and tradition. Journal of Law, Ethics and Public Policy 1: 139–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmela, Mikko. 2011. Can emotions be modeled on perception? Dialectica 65(1): 1–29. doi:10.1111/j.1746-8361.2011.01259.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaub, Miriam. 2010. Das Singuläre und das Exemplarische. Zu Logik und Praxis der Beispiele in Philosophie und Ästhetik. Zürich: Diaphanes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitz, Hermann. 1994. Der gespürte Leib und der vorgestellte Körper. In Wege zu einer volleren Realität. Neue Phänomenologie in der Diskussion, ed. Großheim Michael, 75–92. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Scott. 2011. Legality. Cambridge/London: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Scott. 2014. Massively shared agency. In Rational and social agency. Essays on the philosophy of Michael Bratman, ed. Manuel Vargas and Gideon Yaffe, 257–293. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Barry. 2013. Diagrams, documents, and the meshing of plans. In How to do things with pictures: Skill, practice, performance, ed. András Benedek and Kristóf Nyíri, 165–180. Frankfurt: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max. 1978. Communal and associative relationships. In Economy and society. An outline of interpretive sociology, ed. Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2009. Philosophical investigations (trans: Anscombe, G.E.M., P.M.S. Hacker, and J. Schulte). Malden: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tom Poljanšek .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Poljanšek, T. (2015). Choosing Appropriate Paradigmatic Examples for Understanding Collective Agency. In: Misselhorn, C. (eds) Collective Agency and Cooperation in Natural and Artificial Systems. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 122. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-15515-9_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics