Skip to main content

Concepts Out of Theoretical Contexts

  • Chapter
Relocating the History of Science

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 312))

Abstract

In this paper we take as our point of departure Kostas Gavroglu and Yorgos Goudaroulis’s insight that, in the process of describing and explaining novel phenomena, scientific concepts are taken “out of” their original theoretical context, acquire additional meaning, and become relatively autonomous. We first present their account of how concepts are re-contextualized and, in the process, extended and/or revised. We then situate it within its philosophical context, and discuss how it broke with a long-standing philosophical tradition about concepts. Finally, we argue that recent developments in science studies can flesh out and vindicate the “concepts out of contexts” idea. In particular, historical and philosophical studies of experimentation and cognitive-historical studies of modeling practices indicate various ways in which concepts are formed and articulated “out of context.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a historical survey of the philosophical literature on the meaning of scientific concepts see Arabatzis and Kindi (2013).

  2. 2.

    See, e.g., Carnap (1936), Hempel (1952).

  3. 3.

    Cf. Feyerabend (1960/1999, 18–19, 20–21), Putnam (1962/1975, 217), and Hempel (1973/2001, 212).

  4. 4.

    Cf. Steinle (2009).

  5. 5.

    Cf. Nersessian (1984, 93).

  6. 6.

    Cf. Radder (2006, 121): “the meaning of concepts needs to be articulated when they are being extended or communicated to a novel situation.” Cf. also Rouse (2011).

  7. 7.

    See, e.g., Carnap (1936), Hempel (1952).

  8. 8.

    See, e.g., Suppe (1974), Suppes (1967), van Fraassen (1970).

  9. 9.

    See, e.g., Cartwright (1983), Giere (1988), Morgan and Morrison (1999).

  10. 10.

    See, e.g., Andersen et al. (2006), Darden (1991), Giere (1988), Gooding (1990), Nersessian (1984, 1992, 2008), Thagard (1992), Tweney (1985, 1992).

  11. 11.

    That account has subsequently been further developed and extended to modeling with physical and computational simulations by Nersessian and colleagues in studies of the contemporary model-based reasoning practices in conceptual innovation in the bioengineering sciences (see, e.g., Nersessian 2012). The bioengineering sciences provide fertile ground from which to study conceptual innovation since concepts are routinely taken out of engineering contexts and transferred to explanations and descriptions of biological phenomena, producing abundant paradoxical situations requiring concept formation and change for their resolution.

References

  • Andersen, H., P. Barker, and X. Chen. 2006. The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arabatzis, T. 2006. Representing electrons: A biographical approach to theoretical entities. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arabatzis, T. 2012. Experimentation and the meaning of scientific concepts. In Scientific concepts and investigative practice, ed. U. Feest and F. Steinle, 149–166. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arabatzis, T., and V. Kindi. 2013. The problem of conceptual change in the philosophy and history of science. In International handbook of research on conceptual change, 2nd ed., ed. S. Vosniadou, 343–359. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. 1936. Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science 3: 419–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. 1956. The methodological character of theoretical concepts. In Foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 1, ed. H. Feigl and M. Scriven, 38–76. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. 1983. How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. 1991. Theory change in science: Strategies from Mendelian genetics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, H. 1970. The ‘orthodox’ view of theories. In Theories and methods of physics and psychology, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. IV, ed. M. Radner and S. Winokur, 3–16. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P.K. 1958/1981. An attempt at a realistic interpretation of experience. Repr. in Realism, rationalism and scientific method, Philosophical papers, vol. 1, 17–36. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P.K. 1960/1999. The problem of the existence of theoretical entities. Repr. in Knowledge, science and relativism, Philosophical papers, vol. 3, 16–49. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P.K. 1962/1981. Explanation, reduction and empiricism. Repr. in Realism, rationalism and scientific method, Philosophical papers, vol. 1, 44–96. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P.K. 1965/1981. On the ‘meaning’ of scientific terms. Repr. in Realism, rationalism and scientific method, Philosophical papers, vol. 1, 97–103. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gavroglu, K. 2001. From defiant youth to conformist adulthood: The sad story of liquid helium. Physics in Perspective 3: 165–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gavroglu, K., and Y. Goudaroulis. 1989. Methodological aspects of the development of low temperature physics: Concepts out of contexts. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.N. 1988. Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.N. 1994. The cognitive structure of scientific theories. Philosophy of Science 61: 276–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gooding, D. 1990. Experiment and the making of meaning: Human agency in scientific observation and experiment. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. 1983. Representing and intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heilbron, J.L., and T.S. Kuhn. 1969. The genesis of the Bohr atom. Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 1: 211–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. 1952. Fundamentals of concept formation in empirical science, vol. 2, no. 7. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. 1973/2001. The meaning of theoretical terms: a critique of the standard empiricist construal. Repr. in The philosophy of Carl G. Hempel: Studies in science, explanation, and rationality, ed. J.H. Fetzer, 208–217. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R.A. 1917. The electron: Its isolation and measurement and the determination of some of its properties. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R.A. 1947. Electrons (+ and –), protons, photons, neutrons, mesotrons, and cosmic rays, rev. ed. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M.S., and M. Morrison (eds.). 1999. Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N.J. 1984. Faraday to Einstein: Constructing meaning in scientific theories. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff/Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N.J. 1992. How do scientists think? Capturing the dynamics of conceptual change in science. In Cognitive models of science, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. XV, ed. R. Giere, 3–45. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N.J. 2008. Creating scientific concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N.J. 2012. Modeling practices in conceptual innovation: An ethnographic study of a neural engineering research laboratory. In Scientific concepts and investigative practice, ed. U. Feest and F. Steinle, 245–269. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1962/1975. What theories are not. Repr. in Mathematics, matter and method, Philosophical papers, vol. 1, 215–227. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. 1995. Experimenting in the natural sciences: A philosophical approach. In Scientific practice, ed. J.Z. Buchwald, 56–86. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. 2006. The world observed/the world conceived. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. 2011. Articulating the world: Experimental systems and conceptual understanding. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 25: 243–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinle, F. 2005. Experiment and concept formation. In Logic, methodology and philosophy of science: Proceedings of the twelfth international congress, ed. P. Hájek, L.M. Valdés-Villanueva, and D. Westersthal, 521–536. London: King’s College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinle, F. 2009. How experiments make concepts fail: Faraday and magnetic curves. In Going amiss in experimental research, Boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 267, ed. G. Hon, J. Schickore, and F. Steinle, 119–135. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F., ed. 1974. The structure of scientific theories. 2nd ed. 1977. Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. 1967. What is a scientific theory? In Philosophy of science today, ed. S. Morgenbesser, 55–67. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 1992. Conceptual revolutions. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tweney, R.D. 1985. Faraday’s discovery of induction: A cognitive approach. In Faraday rediscovered, ed. D. Gooding and F.A.J.L. James, 189–210. New York: Stockton Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tweney, R.D. 1992. Stopping time: Faraday and the scientific creation of perceptual order. Physis 29: 149–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B.C. 1970. On the extension of Beth’s semantics of physical theories. Philosophy of Science 37: 325–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B.C. 1980. The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, C.T.R. 1923. Investigations on X-rays and β-rays by the cloud method. Part I. X-rays. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series A 104(724): 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Sections 14.2 and 14.4 above are adapted from Arabatzis (2012). We are indebted to Ana Simões for her helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper. Most of all, we are grateful to Kostas Gavroglu for his loyal friendship over many years. His generous scholarship and our innumerable discussions have been a constant source of inspiration.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Theodore Arabatzis .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Arabatzis, T., Nersessian, N.J. (2015). Concepts Out of Theoretical Contexts. In: Arabatzis, T., Renn, J., Simões, A. (eds) Relocating the History of Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 312. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-14553-2_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics