Skip to main content

Introduction: Objectivity in Science

  • Chapter
  • 2603 Accesses

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 310))

Abstract

While few would question the importance of the objectivity of science for providing a well-supported factual basis upon which policy decisions can be reliably made, it is far from clear what scientific objectivity is or how it should be achieved. In recent decades, questions regarding the objectivity of science have become increasingly salient in framing public debates about science and science policy: for example, can we trust medical research when it is funded by pharmaceutical companies? Or, whose research in climate science meets the standards of scientific objectivity? At the same time, the objectivity of science has become an increasingly important topic among historians and philosophers of science, as well as researchers in related fields in science and technology studies. In the wake of Karl Popper’s (1972) account of objective knowledge and Thomas Kuhn’s (1977) landmark analysis of scientific values in connection with issues of scientific objectivity and rationality, philosophers of science have attempted to clarify questions concerning the role of values in theory choice, the distinction between epistemic (or “cognitive”) and non-epistemic (or “social”) values, and the ways in which different kinds of values (including non-epistemic values) contribute to the objectivity of science. By contrast, historians of science have offered rich historical analyses that aim to clarify the changing historical meanings of objectivity by examining the emergence of particular scientific ideals in specific episodes in the history of science. These historical studies have revealed the complex, multifaceted, and ultimately contingent nature of the ideals that contribute to our current notions and understandings of scientific objectivity. Finally, sociologists and anthropologists of science have offered analyses that explicitly bring into question specific understandings of scientific objectivity as, for example, the disinterestedness or value neutrality of scientific work, by revealing the role of social processes—including the workings of structures of credit, rhetorical practices in science, and the pressure of funding regimes—in the production of scientific knowledge. Taken together, these investigations offer compelling reasons for thinking that scientific objectivity is much more complicated than one might have imagined. Two emergent themes from the science and technology studies literature are especially important in this regard.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For some examples, see Salmon (1980), Hempel (1983), Laudan (1984), McMullin (1988, 1993), Longino (1990, 2002), Kitcher (1995, 2001), Okruhlik (1994), Machamer and Douglas (1998), and Solomon and Richardson (2005).

  2. 2.

    See especially Proctor (1991), Daston and Galison (1992, 2007), and Porter (1995).

  3. 3.

    For example, see Latour and Woolgar (1979), Collins and Pinch (1993), and Latour (1999).

  4. 4.

    For a classic account of the value-free ideal, see Proctor (1991). For more recent elaborations of various philosophical perspectives on the value-free ideal, see Lacey (1999), Machamer and Wolters (2004), Kincaid et al. (2007), and Douglas (2009). For an account of the development of sociology of scientific knowledge by one of its most distinguished practitioners, see Shapin (1995). The Darwin industry cannot be summarized effectively, but a sense of the variety of approaches to contextualizing Darwin’s achievements can be seen in Ruse and Richards (2008).

  5. 5.

    For some important contributions, see Harding (1986, 1991), Longino (1988, 1993), Keller (1989), Haraway (1988), Tuana (1989), Code (1991), and Lloyd (1996).

  6. 6.

    For a representative essay on gender bias within science see Ceci and Williams (2011). An older but more expansive and, sadly, not really superseded treatment is Sonnert and Holton (1995).

  7. 7.

    For the charge against the science and technology studies community see, for example, Koertge (2000) and Gross and Leavitt (1994). An examination of both the work discussed at length and the degree to which that work is actually understood in such scholarship indicates that the views decried were never actually endorsed by the leading members of the science and technology studies community.

  8. 8.

    For discussion of the Climategate scandal, see Montford (2010), Ryghaug and Skjølsvold (2010), and Leiserowitz et al. (2013).

  9. 9.

    The classic texts on underdetermination are Duhem (1906/1954) and Quine (1951/1980). For a more comprehensive and critical discussion of the underdetermination thesis, see Harding (1976), Newton-Smith (1980), Laudan (1990), Laudan and Leplin (1991), Earman (1993), Leplin and Laudan (1993), Kukla (1993), Hoefer and Rosenberg (1994), Gillies (1993, ch. 5), Stanford (2001, 2006), and Intemann (2005).

  10. 10.

    Longino’s advocacy of theoretical pluralism is intended to address the inherently value-laden nature of scientific knowledge, but it is also motivated to address a more general problem, viz., the situated and contextual nature of knowledge. The situatedness of knowledge is, of course, a longstanding feminist concern and the motivation for the standpoint theories of Harding (1986, 1991) and others.

  11. 11.

    For discussion of “historical epistemology,” see Daston (1994). On “matters of fact” from this perspective, see Daston (1991, 1993) and Poovey (1998). On “experience,” see Dear (1995) and Jay (2005).

  12. 12.

    Some high-profile instances of concern about the pharmaceutical industry and its relations to medical research can be found in Healy and Cattell (2003), Angell (2004), and Elliott (2010). For population health more generally, two recent exposés by prominent historians of science are Oreskes and Conway (2010) and Proctor (2012).

References

  • Alcoff, Linda, and Elizabeth Potter, eds. 1993. Feminist epistemologies. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angell, Marcia. 2004. The truth about the drug companies: How they deceive us and what to do about it. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antony, Louise M. 1993. Quine as feminist: The radical import of naturalized epistemology. In A mind of one’s own: Feminist essays on reason and objectivity, eds. Louise M. Antony and Charlotte E. Witt, 185–226. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ceci, Stephen J., and Wendy M. Williams. 2011. Understanding current causes of women’s underrepresentation in science. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 108: 3157–3162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chandler, James, Arnold I. Davidson, and Harry D. Harootunian, eds. 1994. Questions of evidence: Proof, practice, and persuasion across the disciplines. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Code, Lorraine. 1991. What can she know? Feminist theory and the construction of knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry M., and Trevor Pinch. 1993. The Golem: What everyone needs to know about science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, Lorraine. 1991. Baconian facts, academic civility, and the prehistory of objectivity. Annals of Scholarship 8: 337–364.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, Lorraine. 1993. Marvelous facts and miraculous evidence in early modern Europe. In ed. James Chandler et al. 1993, 243–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, Lorraine. 1994. Historical epistemology. In Questions of evidence: Proof, practice, and persuasion across the disciplines, ed. James Chandler, Arnold I. Davidson, and Harry D. Harootunian, 282–289. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, Lorraine, and Peter Galison. 1992. The image of objectivity. Representations 40: 81–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daston, Lorraine, and Peter Galison. 2007/2010. Objectivity. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dear, Peter. 1995. Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the scientific revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, Heather E. 2009. Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, Pierre. 1906/1954. The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory. Trans. Philip P. Wiener. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, John. 1993. Underdetermination, realism, and reason. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 18: 19–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, Carl. 2010. White coat, black hat: Adventures on the dark side of medicine. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, Donald. 1993. Philosophy of science in the twentieth century: Four central themes. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, Paul R., and Norman Levitt. 1994. Higher superstition: The academic left and its quarrels with science. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian. 1999. The social construction of what? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, Donna. 1988. Situated knowledges: The science question in feminism and the privilege of partial perspective. Feminist Studies 14: 575–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harding, Sandra, ed. 1976. Can theories be refuted? Essays on the Duhem-Quine thesis. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, Sandra. 1986. The science question in feminism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, Sandra. 1991. Whose science? Whose knowledge? Thinking from women’s lives. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, Sandra. 1992. After the neutrality ideal: Science, politics, and ‘Strong Objectivity’. Social Research 59: 567–587.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, Sandra. 1993. Rethinking standpoint epistemology: ‘What is Strong Objectivity’? In Feminist epistemologies, eds. Linda Alcoff and Elizabeth Potter, 49–82. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healy, David, and Dinah Cattell. 2003. The interface between authorship, industry, and science in the domain of therapeutics. British Journal of Psychiatry 182: 22–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 1983. Kuhn and Salmon on rationality and theory choice. Journal of Philosophy 80: 570–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, Carl, and Alexander Rosenberg. 1994. Empirical equivalence, underdetermination, and systems of the world. Philosophy of Science 61: 592–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Intemann, Kristen. 2005. Feminism, underdetermination, and values in science. Philosophy of Science 72: 1001–1012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jay, Martin. 2005. Songs of experience: Modern American and European variations on a universal theme. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, Evelyn Fox. 1985. Reflections on gender and science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, Harold, John Dupré, and Alison Wylie, eds. 2007. Value-free science? Ideals and illusions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip. 1995. The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip. 2001. Science, truth, and democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koertge, Noretta, ed. 2000. A house built on sand: Exposing postmodernist myths about science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. 1977. Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. In The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific tradition and change, 320–339. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, André. 1993. Laudan, Leplin, empirical equivalence, and underdetermination. Analysis 53: 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, Hugh. 1999. Is science value-free? Values and scientific understanding. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, Bruno. 1999. Pandora’s hope: Essays in the reality of science studies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, Bruno, and Steve Woolgar. 1979. Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts. Beverly Hills: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, Larry. 1984. Science and values: The aims of science and their role in scientific debate. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, Larry. 1990. Demystifying underdetermination. In ed. Wade C. Savage, 1990, 267–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, Larry, and Jarrett Leplin. 1991. Empirical equivalence and underdetermination. Journal of Philosophy 88: 449–472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, Larry, and Jarrett Leplin. 1993. Determination undeterred: Reply to Kukla. Analysis 53: 8–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leiserowitz, Anthony A., Edward W. Maibach, Connie Roser-Renouf, Nicholas Smith, and Erica Dawson. 2013. Climategate, public opinion, and the loss of trust. American Behavioral Scientist 57: 818–837.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, Elisabeth. 1996. Science and anti-science: Objectivity and its real enemies. In Feminism, science and the philosophy of science, eds. Lynn Hankinson Nelson and Jack Nelson, 217–259. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, Helen E. 1988. Review essay: Science, objectivity, and feminist values. Feminist Studies 14: 561–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, Helen E. 1990. Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, Helen E. 1993. Subjects, power, and knowledge: Description and prescription in feminist philosophies of science. In Feminist epistemologies, eds. Linda Alcoff and Elizabeth Potter, 101–120. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, Helen E. 2002. The fate of knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, Peter, and Heather Douglas. 1998. How values are in science. Critical Quarterly 40: 29–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, Peter K., and Gereon Wolters, eds. 2004. Science, values, and objectivity. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, Ernan, ed. 1988. Construction and constraint: The shaping of scientific rationality. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, Ernan. 1993. Rationality and paradigm change in science. In World changes: Thomas Kuhn and the nature of science, ed. Paul Horwich, 55–78. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montford, A.W. 2010. The hockey stick illusion: Climategate and the corruption of science. London: Stacey International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton-Smith, William. 1980. The underdetermination of theory by data. In Rationality of science: Studies in the foundations of science and ethics, ed. Risto Hilpinen, 91–110. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okruhlik, Kathleen. 1994. Gender and the biological sciences. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20 (suppl): 21–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, Naomi, and Erik M. Conway. 2010. Merchants of doubt: How a handful of scientists obscured the truth on issues from tobacco smoke to global warming. New York: Bloomsbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poovey, Mary. 1998. A history of the modern fact: Problem of knowledge in the sciences of wealth and society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Karl R. 1972. Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, Theodore M. 1995. Trust in numbers: The pursuit of objectivity in science and public life. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proctor, Robert N. 1991. Value-free science? Purity and power in modern knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proctor, Robert N. 2012. Golden holocaust: Origins of the cigarette catastrophe and the case for abolition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard V. 1951/1980. Two dogmas of Empiricism. The Philosophical Review 60: 20–43. Repr. in From a logical point of view, 2nd ed., 20–46. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, Michael, and Robert J. Richards, eds. 2008. The Cambridge companion to Darwin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryghaug, Marianne, and Tomas Moe Skjølsvold. 2010. The global warming of climate science: Climategate and the construction of scientific facts. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 24: 287–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, Wesley C. 1980. Rationality and objectivity in science or Tom Kuhn meets Tom Bayes. In Scientific theories. Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science 14, ed. Wade C. Savage, 175–204. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage, Wade C. ed. 1980. Scientific theories. Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science 14. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven. 1995. Here and everywhere: Sociology of scientific knowledge. Annual Review of Sociology 21: 289–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven. 2010. Science and the modern world. In Never pure: Historical studies of science as if it was produced by people with bodies, situated in time, space, culture, and society, and struggling for credibility and authority, 377–391. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Miriam, and Alan Richardson. 2005. Essay review: A critical context for Longino’s critical contextual empiricism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 36: 211–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sonnert, Gerhard, and Gerald J. Holton. 1995. Who succeeds in science? The gender dimension. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, Kyle P. 2001. Refusing the devil’s Bargain: What kind of underdetermination should we take seriously? Philosophy of Science 68: S1–S12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, Kyle P. 2006. Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuana, Nancy, ed. 1989. Feminism & science. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This volume grew out of a series of initiatives of the Situating Science: Humanist and Social Scientific Studies of Science knowledge Cluster Grant, funded by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (SSHRC). This multi-year, multi-site grant is administered at the University of King’s College/Dalhousie University in Halifax; Gordon McOuat is the principal investigator and Emily Tector is the project manager. This grant brought two of the editors, Jonathan Tsou and Flavia Padovani, to the University of British Columbia as postdoctoral fellows and funded the Objectivity in Science Conference in June 2010. The third editor, Alan Richardson, is the BC node manager for this grant and would like to thank McOuat and Tector for their support and Nissa Bell and Simone Dharmaratne for their able assistance in all matters of grant administration at UBC. All the efforts around this project including conference organization and the preparation of this volume were aided by the project research assistant, Dani Hallet. While this project was on-going, Alan Richardson had the good fortune to supervise the dissertation by Jill Fellows on objectivity entitled “Making Up Knowers: Objectivity and Categories of Epistemic Subjects” (UBC 2011)—the final product and the conversations leading to it have substantially informed his understanding of the recent literature on objectivity. Flavia Padovani wishes to acknowledge financial support from the Swiss National Science Foundation grant PA00P1–134177 and would also like to thank the Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science at the London School of Economics for providing stimulating environment where part of this work has been carried out. Jonathan Y. Tsou is grateful for research support from the Center of Excellence in the Arts and Humanities (CEAH) at Iowa State University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan Y. Tsou .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Tsou, J.Y., Richardson, A., Padovani, F. (2015). Introduction: Objectivity in Science. In: Padovani, F., Richardson, A., Tsou, J. (eds) Objectivity in Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 310. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-14349-1_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics