Skip to main content

Enforcement Deflection and Innovation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Law, Development and Innovation

Part of the book series: SxI - Springer for Innovation / SxI - Springer per l'Innovazione ((SXIINNO,volume 13))

Abstract

Enforcement and innovation are both usually associated with development and deemed desirable. Relationship between them is, however, less than smooth and peaceful. Some enforcement issues, although general, show particularly critical when facing innovation. Law and regulation usually take into account only a limited set of features of human activities and their products to trigger enforcement mechanisms. Herein, they are called anchor properties. If the option is cheap, there are strong incentives for interested parties to manipulate them. Result of these actions, being privately beneficial, is socially detrimental. The term deflection is used in this work to name that effect. Actions intended to deflect enforcement can be illegal, as the ones included within the doctrine of evasion in Anglo-Saxon systems (in France, fraude à la loi, in Spain, fraude de ley, in Germany, Rechtswidrige Umgehung eines Gesetzes) or even legal. Rationally turning into judgment proof is an emblematic instance of this behavior and a good benchmark to model their effects. Innovation can, and usually does, alter present relations between levels of activity/care and levels of harm, as well as correspondence between those levels and anchor properties taken as representative of them. That dynamics gives place to enforcement problems and, in special, peculiar instances of deflection. Deflection increases social costs by several ways. On the one hand, by weaken deterrence. On the other, and related to innovation, deflecting enforcement of schemes designed to promote innovation distorts competition between present and new technologies. Both, increase social cost. Moreover, some usual strategies intuitively intended to cut down chances of deflection (second-order enforcement strategies and rising the amount of sanctions) can be less efficient than rival frameworks, because they disregard some non-obvious costs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Sect. 7.

  2. 2.

    This usage of the term is not shared by scholars who reject the idea of pre-legal rights as a notion relevant for legal theory (broadly speaking legal positivists). Those who admit the natural or spontaneous origin of rights can and usually do, use the term enforcement in the second meaning too, in different contexts.

  3. 3.

    This conceptual branch may be, in turn, split into one in which the fine is imposed and collected, and other wherein it is not. The latter is a good part of the following development.

  4. 4.

    i.e., Argentina and Brazil. As it is known, there is a variety of schemes on the matter depending on the state organization.

  5. 5.

    And some entanglement of Humean realms of ought and is that the previous statement conveys.

  6. 6.

    A set of instances of conduct of the same class, i.e. car speeding, can be described as a range of conducts.

  7. 7.

    The same applies to any alternative aim perused by the institutional framework. For simplicity’s sake, hereinafter I will refer only to efficiency aims.

  8. 8.

    Level of harm is also a dependent variable, but is not under control of policy makers.

  9. 9.

    Anyway, a system of this kind could be even a good option in social terms. The social cost of under-deterrence could be less than the gains in reduction of monitoring cost.

  10. 10.

    For simplicity’s sake I am disregarding reputation costs, symbolic effect et cetera.

  11. 11.

    Homestead Declaration refers to a form filed with the county recorder’s office to put on record one’s right to a homestead exemption. A homestead declaration protects a person’s home from being seized and sold in the event a money judgment is entered against him/her by a court.

  12. 12.

    Law number 14432, 2012.

  13. 13.

    Demsetz and Alchian say “…What is owned are rights to use resources, including one’s body and mind, and these rights are always circumscribed, often by the prohibition of certain actions…The strength with which rights are owned can be defined by the extent to which an owner’s decision about how a resource will be used actually determines the use. If the probability is “1” that an owner's choice of how a particular right should be exercised actually dominates the decision process that governs actual use, then that owner can be said to own absolutely the particular right under consideration…..” (Demsetz and Alchian 1973). It is easy to see that while the first statement pertains to the field of “ought” statements, probability statements, as the second one, are of the kind of “is” statements in Hume’s taxonomy.

  14. 14.

    It can be a monetary benefit as in the case of the benefit of a firm or a simple increase in utility, even mere pleasure and not a rise in money in the case of an individual.

  15. 15.

    The level of precaution is expressed in money units, so can be exchanged by precaution cost.

  16. 16.

    As it is known, the expression unilateral accidents, assumes that causation of harm depends only on the tortfeasor. In a previous work, it was suggested that unilateral causation would be more precise to denote the same case. Indeed, the opposite (bilateral accidents) might not be clear. According to the common usage of words, either cases in which two agents cause harm each other or those where there is only a victim, but his or her harm is caused partly by him or herself and partly by the injurer, could be deemed bilateral. The apparent paradox to common sense is that the usual usage of the term addresses only the latter, being the former (probably the most “bilateral” in usual terms) a case of two unilateral accidents.

  17. 17.

    The value of those assets, indeed; \(h\) also stands for harm’s value.

  18. 18.

    For the sake of brevity, this model includes some implicit assumptions. Sometimes, precaution cost is non-monetary. On the contrary, if it is explicitly monetary, executable assets would be only \(y - x\). Additionally, it is also assumed that the benefit is either non-monetary or may be hidden at no cost. Otherwise, executable assets will be \(y + g\).

  19. 19.

    For a complete review of the relevant literature, see (Ganuza and Gomez 2004).

  20. 20.

    This can be seen by comparing the first order conditions of this issue with the first order condition previously shown.

  21. 21.

    Ancient highest court decisions as Gregory v. Helvering, 293 U.S. 465 (1935), by creating the “substance over form doctrine” in taxation, can be appreciated as increasing private deflection cost, as herein defined, and then, tending to fix this source of inefficiency. A brief discussion on the rival instruments to deal with this effect will be sketched in further paragraphs.

  22. 22.

    European Council Directive of 25 July 1985 on the approximation of the laws, regulations and administrative provisions of the Member States concerning liability for defective products (85/374/EEC), 7.

  23. 23.

    There would be also incentives for some firms to cartelize under certain conditions, what is outside the scope of this work.

  24. 24.

    Only for simplicity reasons I am intentionally omitting probability of detection of harm and other refinements.

References

  • Acciarri HA, Castellano A (2005) Mandatory third party insurance: god, the devil, and the details. Berkeley program in law & economics. Latin American and Caribbean Law and Economics Association (ALACDE) Annual papers, paper 9. http://repositories.cdlib.org/bple/alacde/9

  • Acciarri HA, Castellano A, Barbero A (2006) Daños y Costos Sociales: el Problema de los Judgment Proof como una Alternativa de Elección. Berkeley program in law & economics. Latin American and Caribbean Law and Economics Association (ALACDE) Annual papers, paper 37. http://repositories.cdlib.org/bple/alacde/37/

  • Acemoglu D, Garcia-Jimeno C, Robinson JA (2014) State capacity and economic development: a network approach. National Bureau of Economic Research, Working Paper No. 19813. http://www.nber.org/papers/w19813

  • Alchian A (1965) Some economics of property rights. Il Politico 30(4):816–829 (in Economic forces at work: selected works. Liberty Press, Indianapolis)

    Google Scholar 

  • Arlen J (1992) Should defendants’ wealth matter? J Legal Stud 21:413–429

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS (1968) Crime and punishment: an economic approach. J Polit Econ 76:169–217

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buscaglia E (1994) Legal and economic development: the missing links. J Inter-Am Stud World Aff 4(35):20–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Buscaglia, Van Dijk (2003) Controlling organized crime and corruption in the public sector. Forum Crime Soc 3(1, 2):3–34. http://www.unodc.org/pdf/crime/forum/forum3_Art1.pdf

  • Calabresi G (1970) The costs of accidents. A legal and economic analysis. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Chekera YT, Nmehielle VO (2013) The international law principle of permanent sovereignty over natural resources as an instrument for development: the case of Zimbabwean diamonds. Afr J Legal Stud 6(18)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooter R, Acciarri HA (eds) (2012) Introducción al Análisis Económico del Derecho. Civitas-Legal Publishing-Thomson Reuters, Santiago de Chile, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooter R, Ulen T (1997) Law & economics, 2nd edn. Addison-Wesley, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Dari-Mattiacci G, De Geest G (2002) An analysis of the judgement proof problem under different tort models. German working papers in law and economics

    Google Scholar 

  • Dari-Mattiacci G, De Geest G (2003) When will judgment proof injurers take too much precaution? George Mason law & economics research, Paper No. 03-56. http://ssrn.com/abstract=477042

  • De Geest G, Dari-Mattiacci G (2002) On the combined use of anti-judgement-proof regulation and tort law. Working Paper, Utrecht University

    Google Scholar 

  • Demsetz H, Alchian A (1973) The property right paradigm. J Econ Hist 33(1):16–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewees D, Duff D, Trebilcock M (1996) Exploring the domain of accident law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ganuza JJ, Gomez F (2004) Optimal negligence rule under limited liability. UPF. www.econ.upf.edu/docs/papers/downloads/759.pdf

  • Garoupa N (1997) The theory of optimal law enforcement. J Econ Surv 11:267–295

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg T (2000) Does law matter for economic development? Evidence from East Asia. Law Soc Rev 34(3):829–856

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1738) A treatise of human nature. John Noon at the White-Hart, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Innes R (1999) Optimal liability with stochastic harms, judgement-proof injurers, and asymmetric information. Int Rev Law Econ 19:181–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jost PJ (1996) Limited liability and the requirement to purchase insurance. Int Rev Law Econ 16:259–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levitsky S, Murillo MV (eds) (2006) Argentine democracy: the politics of institutional weakness. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis T, Sappington D (1999) Using decoupling and deep pockets to mitigate judgement-proof problems. Int Rev Law Econ 19:275–293

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miceli T, Segerson K (2003) A note on optimal care by wealth-constrained injurers. Int Rev Law Econ 23(3):273–284

    Google Scholar 

  • Nmehielle VO, Madhava Menon NR (2014) Opportunity, inclusion, and equity as imperatives for meaningful law and justice-guided development. In: Cissé H, Madhava Menon NR, Cordonier Segger M-C, Nmehielle VO (eds) The World Bank legal review. Fostering development through opportunity, inclusion, and equity, vol 5

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson M (1993) Dictatorship, Democracy, and Development. Am Polit Sci Rev 87(3):567–576

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitchford R (1995) How liable should a lender be? The case of judgement-proof firms and environmental risk. Am Econ Rev 85:1171–1186

    Google Scholar 

  • Polborn M (1998) Mandatory insurance and the judgment-proof problem. Int Rev Law Econ 18:141–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polinsky AM, Shavell S (2000) The economic theory of public enforcement of law. J Econ Lit 38:45–76

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polinsky AM, Shavell S (2001) Corruption and optimal law enforcement. J Public Econ 81:1–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polinsky AM, Shavell S (2007) Handbook of law and economics, vol 1. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (1983) Development: which way now? Econ J 93:745, 748

    Google Scholar 

  • Shavell S (1987) Economic analysis of accident law. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shavell S (2004a) Foundations of economic analysis of law. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shavell S (2004b) Minimum asset requirements and compulsory liability insurance as solutions to the judgment-proof problem. National Bureau of Economic Research, Working Paper 10341

    Google Scholar 

  • Summers J (1983) The case of the disappearing defendant: an economic analysis. Univ Pa Law Rev 132:145–185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • United Nation General Assembly (1986) Res/41/128, Declaration on the right to development

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hugo A. Acciarri .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Acciarri, H.A. (2016). Enforcement Deflection and Innovation. In: Bellantuono, G., Lara, F. (eds) Law, Development and Innovation. SxI - Springer for Innovation / SxI - Springer per l'Innovazione, vol 13. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-13311-9_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-13311-9_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-13310-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-13311-9

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics