Skip to main content

Bit from It

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
It From Bit or Bit From It?

Part of the book series: The Frontiers Collection ((FRONTCOLL))

Abstract

With his aphorism ‘it from bit’, Wheeler argued that anything physical, any it, ultimately derives its very existence entirely from discrete detector-elicited information-theoretic answers to yes or no quantum binary choices: bits. In this spirit, many theorists now give ontological primacy to information. To test the idea, I identify three distinct kinds of information and find that things, not information, are primary. Examination of what Wheeler meant by ‘it’ and ‘bit’ then leads me to invert his aphorism: ‘bit’ derives from ‘it’. I argue that this weakens but not necessarily destroys the argument that nature is fundamentally digital and continuity an illusion. There may also be implications for the interpretation of quantum mechanics and the nature of time, causality and the world (For publication in this volume, I have added some new footnotes, dated 2014, in which I indicate developments in my thinking since the essay competition, giving details of any appropriate publications. I also take the opportunity, omitted at the time, to respond to some of the comments that were made of my essay in FQXi posts (at http://fqxi.org/community/forum/topic/911). I have also, without noting them, made a few trivial changes to the text for the sake of greater clarity and precision).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    2014: The ‘from a particular point of view’ is unfortunate and in conflict with my actual position expressed in Sect. General Comments. It slipped in through my enthusiasm for Leibniz, for whom sentient beings (monads) are the ‘true atoms of existence’. As I will spell out in further footnotes, especially 14, below (which take into account quantum mechanics), my working assumption is now rather precisely that our internal perceptions are a partial reflection—a particular point of view—of an external universe that is a collection of shapes. Both the individual shapes and their collection, which I call shape space, are holistic concepts.

  2. 2.

    2014. In a discussion post, Tom McFarlane commented “there are often multiple distinct explanations for the same phenomena, i.e., under-determination of theory by the facts”. In response, I would distinguish between contrived theories, which one need not take seriously, and more solid theories. For example, many theoreticians are currently exploring sensible alternatives to Einstein’s general theory of relativity that are all compatible with presently known phenomena. To the extent they succeed, one can have provisional belief in the external world they assume. My general thesis does not depend on the specific kind of external reality in which currently I personally believe.

  3. 3.

    Verbs by themselves have no meaning. In the sentence “Bit dog man” (the standard order in Irish Gaelic), we would not know what ‘bit’ means had we not seen canine teeth in action.

  4. 4.

    On von Neumann’s advice, Shannon also called it entropy by analogy with Boltzmann’s entropy in statistical mechanics.

  5. 5.

    Appendix A gives a different example of semantic content generated by a timeless law.

  6. 6.

    In relativity, fundamentally defined ‘nows’ are denied. However, in the actual universe cosmologists can and do define them using the distribution of matter.

  7. 7.

    In the absence of a viable hidden-variables explanation of quantum phenomena, it does appear that quantum probabilities have a better ‘birthright’ than the ignorance of classical physics to appear in the expression (17.1) for information. However, I do not think that this affects the main thrust of my argument.

  8. 8.

    2014: In a thoughful post on my comments here, Christinel Stoica defends Wheeler and argues that his It-from-Bit idea must be understood in the conceptual framework of ‘delayed-choice’ experiments. Christinel’s observations certainly help to clarify Wheeler’s intuition (and I recommend the reader to have a look at them), but I feel my critique of Wheeler’s aphorism stands: his hits of electrons on screens are not Shannon bits and they are not individual binary digits either. It might have helped had I been more explicit about my basic ‘many-instants’ interpretation [7] of quantum mechanics.

  9. 9.

    For the arguments of the following section, it is important that qubits are in stationary quantum states, for which the probabilities are defined by the time-independent Schrödinger equation. One has timeless probabilities for possible configurations.

  10. 10.

    Nature may be both; space appears to have three dimensions but to be continuous.

  11. 11.

    As of now, the best candidates are configurations of fields defined on a manifold that carries a three-metric. In essence, these are not unlike what we see when we open eyes.

  12. 12.

    2014: At the time this essay was being written, I did not refer to an important change in my thinking about time and configurations that was taking place. This was partly because my ideas were still developing but more importantly because the change did not in any way affect the main argument of the essay. However, let me here briefly indicate the nature of the change, which can be illustrated by the problem of three point particles that interact through Newton’s law of gravitation. At any instant, the three particles form a triangle, which can be represented by two angles, which define its shape, and a further number which defines its size (area). Now the latter is a dimensionful quantity that depends on an arbitrary definition of the unit of length, say inch or centimeter. If the three particles are taken to model the universe, size can have no meaning. One needs to make a clear distinction between the shape of the triangle, defined by two dimensionless angles, and its size. By configuration in my earlier work, I included the size of the considered system. In my more recent work with collaborators, I have come to regard only the shape as fundamental. We formulate the dynamics of the universe as shape dynamics. Size still plays a role, but only as a dimensionless ratio of sizes at different epochs. This ratio then appears as an internal time variable. I cannot go into the many interesting consequences of this change of perspective, but instead refer the reader to the papers [1015]. I will only say that if I were to write the essay now, I would replace the word ‘configuration’ in what follows by ‘shape’. With one exception that I will indicate, the points I want to make would not be changed.

  13. 13.

    2014: In line with the comments made in footnote 12, I would now express this somewhat differently since the presence of an internal time is compatible with a certain notion of causality. Many pages would be needed to make this clear. For the moment I refer the reader to [15].

  14. 14.

    This idea requires amplification! Let me just say that the time-independent Schrödinger equation determines the most probable shapes of molecules. It is at least possible [7] that an analogous timeless equation for the universe gives the highest probability to configurations with shapes that carry semantic information. 2014: I think this could still be true with a time-dependent, as opposed to timeless, equation of the kind we expect in shape dynamics (see footnote 12 and [15]), though now it will be necessary to say that nature will find pretty shells both ‘now and then’ as well as ‘here and there’. This gives me an opportunity to keep to the promise made in footnote 1 and also respond to the post of Anonymous, who doubted whether “all information exists in external reality and is merely transmitted to the consciousness ...Some information is internally generated.” I’m not sure where Anonmymous draws the line between ‘external’ and ‘internal’, but for me the latter is everything that I experience. I am acutely aware that, at any instant, I have no control over what I will actually experience in the next instant though it does seem to fit into an at least partially coherent history. I assume that there is psychophysical parallelism, meaning that to everything which I experience there corresponds a mathematically structured external reality in which what I experience is ‘encoded’. Thus, a ‘super-mathematician’ who could examine the full external reality could deduce what I experience in any instant. The external reality I conjecture is dualistic: a timeless realm of possible shapes of the universe and a wave function \(\psi \) defined on it that passes through a succession of states. By this I mean that in a given state each shape has a certain value of \(\psi \) and that the distribution of the \(|\psi |\) values over the possible shapes changes continuously from one state to the next. In [7] I suggested that the values of \(\psi \) are defined on configurations and are timeless: fixed once and for all. I further conjectured that the distribution of the \(\psi \) values is very nonuniform, with the Born probability amplitude \(|\psi |^2\) being concentrated on what I called time capsules: configurations whose structure is so special as to suggest that they must have arisen through a history governed by definite physical laws. I assumed further that our brains are, in any instant, embedded, in such time capsules and are themselves time capsules. Then my conjectured psychophysical parallelism related our vibrant experience of change to the rich structure of our time-capsule brain. To be precise, I conjectured that consciousness transforms information in static structure—being—into experienced change—becoming. I am still trying to digest the implications of my new belief that there is an effective internal time in the physics of the universe. One thing at least I can say is that the results of [15] do suggest that the wave function of the universe may well have an intrinsic propensity to give high values of \(|\psi |^2\) to shapes of the universe that are time capsules.

References

  1. J.A. Wheeler, Sakharov revisited: “It from Bit”. Proceedings of the First International A D Sakharov Memorial Conference on Physics, Moscow, USSR, ed. by M. Man’ko (Nova Science Publishers, Commack, 1991), pp. 27–31

    Google Scholar 

  2. V. Vedral, Decoding Reality: The Universe as Quantum Information (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2010)

    Google Scholar 

  3. P.C. Davies, N.H. Gregerson (eds.), Information and the Nature of Reality (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2010)

    Google Scholar 

  4. J. Barbour, The Discovery of Dynamics (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2001)

    Google Scholar 

  5. E. Shannon, W. Weaver, The Mathematical Theory of Communication (University of Illinois Press, Urbana and Chicago, 1963)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. J.R. Pierce, An Introduction to Information Theory, 2nd edn. (Dover Publications, New York, 1980)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. J. Barbour, The End of Time (Weidenfeld and Nicolson, London, Oxford University Press, New York, 1999)

    Google Scholar 

  8. D. Deutsch, It from qubit, in Science and Ultimate Reality, ed. by J. Barrow, D. Davies, C. Harper (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2003)

    Google Scholar 

  9. A. Zeilinger, Dance of the Photons (Farrar, Strauss and Giroux, New York, 2010)

    Google Scholar 

  10. J. Barbour, N.Ó. Murchadha, Classical and quantum gravity on conformal superspace (1999), gr-qc/9911071

  11. E. Anderson, J. Barbour, B.Z. Foster, B. Kelleher, N.Ó. Murchadha, The physical gravitational degrees of freedom. Class. Quant. Gravity 22, 1795–1802 (2005), arXiv:gr-qc/0407104

  12. H. Gomes, S. Gryb, T. Koslowski, Einstein gravity as a 3D conformally invariant theory. Class. Quant. Gravity 28, 045005 (2011), arXiv:1010.2481

  13. J. Barbour, Shape dynamics: an introduction. In Quantum Field Theory and Gravity. Proceedings of Conference at Regensburg 2010 (Birkhäuser, 2012), ed. by F. Finster et al.

    Google Scholar 

  14. J. Barbour, T. Koslowski, F. Mercati, The solution to the problem of time in shape dynamics (Accepted for publication in Class. Quant. Gravity 2014) (2013), arXiv: 1302.6264 [gr-qc]

  15. J. Barbour, T. Koslowski, F. Mercati, A gravitational origin of the arrows of time. arXiv:1310.5167 [gr-qc]

  16. H.G. Alexander (ed.), The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 1956)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. J. Barbour, The deep and suggestive principles of Leibnizian philosophy (downloadable from platonia.com). Harvard Rev. Philos. 11, 45–58 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  18. J. Barbour, Dynamics of pure shape, relativity and the problem of time. Lect. Notes Phys. 633 15–35 (2003), gr-qc/0309089

  19. J. Barbour, The nature of time, Winner of first juried prize essay of The Foundational Questions Institute (fqxi.org) (2009), arXiv:0903.3489 [gr-qc]

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Julian Barbour .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendices

Appendix A: Maximal Variety

In the body of the essay, I describe ‘time capsules’ as configurations that carry intrinsic semantic content. Here I give another example. It does not suggest history, but the notion of a structured configuration is all important.

Leibniz told princesses that we live in the best of all possible worlds, but in his serious philosophy he argued that we lived in the one that is more varied than any possible alternative (Monadology, §58). Some years ago, Lee Smolin and I found a way to express this idea in a simple mathematical model. One representation is in terms of a ring of \(N\) slots (here \(N=24\)) into which balls of different colours (or darkness in grey shades) can be placed (Fig. 17.1).

Fig. 17.1
figure 1

The most varied two-colour (dark-light) 24-slot universe

The diagram is maximally varied in the sense that, without pointing to a particular ball or naming colours or sense of direction, each ball is more readily identified than for any other occupation of the slots. The rule of creation is minimization of indifference (the inverse of variety). Balls are identified by their neighbourhoods: the seven-slot neighbourhood centered on ball \(x\) at noon is either the string \(SDDxDSD\) or \(DSDxDDS\) (left-right symmetry), where \(S\) and \(D\) are same (\(S\)) or different (\(D\)) neighbours (colour symmetry). The indifference \(I_{ij}\) of slots \(i\) and \(j\) is equal to the length (3, 5, 7,\(\ldots \)) of the respective strings needed to distinguish them. The total indifference of a distribution is \(I=\sum _{i<j}\,I_{ij}\). The most varied distribution is the one for which \(I\) has its smallest value. The relative number of balls of each colour is not fixed in advance but found by the minimization of \(I\). Figure 17.1 is typical of the maximal-variety configurations (in general there are 2 or 3 for each \(N\), though for 24 Fig. 17.1 is the unique configuration). Interestingly, the symmetric rule of creation invariably leads to markedly asymmetric configurations. The maximally—and near-maximally—varied configurations ‘proclaim their own sematics’ in the sense that smart enough mathematicians could deduce the law that creates them. For more details and the results of calculations up to \(N=27\) see [17].

Appendix B: Best Matching

This appendix describes the motion of particles without the props of absolute space and time. Position and time are treated relationally. The basic idea—best matching—also leads to general relativity (GR) [18]. The further requiremnt of relativity of size leads to GR with a distinguished definition of simultaneity [11]. I relied on this result in Sect. Holism and Reductionism to argue that identifying instants of time with confgurations is not in conflict with Einstein’s theory.

Consider \(N\) gravitating particles (masses \(m_i\)) in Euclidean space. For \(N=3\), Fig. 17.2 shows the three particles at the vertices of the triangles representing two possible relative configurations ‘held in imagination’ somehow relative to each other. This generates apparent displacements \(\delta \mathbf x _i\) of particle \(i\). Calculate (17.2):

Fig. 17.2
figure 2

A trial placing of the two triangles generates apparent displacements \(\delta \mathbf x _i\). Minimization of the trial action (17.2) leads to the best-matched displacements

$$\begin{aligned} \delta A_{trial}=2\sqrt{(E-V)\sum _i{m_i\over 2}\delta \mathbf x _i\cdot \delta \mathbf x _i}, ~ V=-\sum _{i<j}{m_im_j\over r_{ij}}. \end{aligned}$$
(17.2)

Here \(E\) is a constant. The action (17.2) is clearly arbitrary with no significance, but, using Euclidean translations and rotations, we can move either triangle relative to the other into the unique best-matched position that minimizes (17.2). For any two nearly identical triangles, the best-matched value of (17.2) defines a ‘distance’ between them and a metric on \(\mathcal S\), the space of all possible relative configurations of the particles. One can then find the geodesics in \(\mathcal S\) with respect to this intrinsically—and holistically—defined metric of the \(N\)-body universe.

It can be shown [17] that the relative motions which the particles undergo as the representative point of the system moves along the geodesic are identical to the observable relative motions of particles in the Newtonian \(N\)-body problem with total energy \(E\) and vanishing total angular momentum. Moreover, the increment \(\delta t\) of ‘Newtonian’ time is derived [19]:

$$\begin{aligned} \delta t=\sqrt{\sum _i\,m_i\delta \mathbf x _i\cdot \delta \mathbf x _i\over {2(E-V)}}. \end{aligned}$$
(17.3)

The combination of best matching and the geodesic requirement, which dispenses with Newton’s absolute time as independent variable, leads to recovery of Newtonian behaviour of subsystems in a large \(N\)-body ‘island universe’. Newton’s first law, the basis of reductionism, is holistic in origin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Barbour, J. (2015). Bit from It. In: Aguirre, A., Foster, B., Merali, Z. (eds) It From Bit or Bit From It?. The Frontiers Collection. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-12946-4_17

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics