Skip to main content

Some Reflections on the Origin of Reason Through an Outline of the Genealogy of Language in the Light of Homonymity, Analogy, and Metaphor

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Interdisciplinary Studies in Pragmatics, Culture and Society

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 4))

Abstract

The origin of reason through an outline of the genealogy of language in the light of homonymity, analogy, and metaphor.

In this chapter, I try to show that reason as a cognitive capacity primarily functions through the use of homonyms. The argument is based on the fact that experience is created through the chiastic interrelation between world and body-mind as it is documented by the historical precedence of the verb in relation to the substantive. This creative modus operandi invests the mind with a catalogue of virtual aspects of sense incorporated in the word complex which represents them centered in the root. Thus, a Proto-Indo-European (PIE) root like “*ghabh-” contains the double sense of “to hold,” which is either to take, and grasp, or to give and yield. This metaphorical core sense—probably inferred from the hand, since gabhasti means “hand” or “forearm” in Sanskrit—produces other aspects of sense like “begivenhed” in Danish, meaning “event,” and also “habit,” the way to “have,” or to accommodate oneself to the occurrences in life. What I claim is that reason is the capacity to understand and hence by meta-reflection to choose deliberately between such senses, in particular relating to their value basis, because reason also is involved as their principle of origin—qua practical reason—through which this metaphorical richness was originally coined. These principles of construction and deconstruction may also be applied to the analysis of reason itself since it also has a homonymic basis in the metaphors of air and light.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    John Dewey suggested this line of thinking in his pragmatic epistemology by defining the essence of perception as aesthetic (Dewey 2005). The German philosopher Ernst Cassirer (Cassirer 1923) was another important exponent of this paradigm.

  2. 2.

    J. G. Herder must probably be credited with shaping the idea that conceptualization is a function of the metaphorical use of perception. Like Locke, Herder saw sensation as producing all our concepts, but explained the abstract and nonempirical concept as the product of the capacity to create homonyms (Herder 2002).

  3. 3.

    Jacob L. Mey suggested the concept “wording” many years ago: “By ‘wording’ I will understand the process through which human beings enter the world by their use of language” (Mey 1985, p. 166).

  4. 4.

    It is remarkable that two of the most powerful theories of language from the last century, the one of Maurice Merleau-Ponty and the one of Ludwig Wittgenstein, presuppose that language is a function of expression, thus abstracting from the concept of language as “synthetic” in Aristotle’s sense, as a contingent system in relation to semantic genealogy. Only the Stoics tried to seriously counter this view, despite the fact that their grammatical masterpieces that often strayed into onomatopoeic fantasies. However, in “Cratylus,” Plato anticipated the critique of the “synthḗké” which would become the trademark of Saussure’s theory. Merleau-Ponty developed his thoueghts on the origin of language based on his deep knowledge of child psychology; Wittgenstein’s casual remarks probably just intended to escape the label theory, which haunted him. The expression theory of language is, of course, rather banal, and impossible to corroborate, open to various perverse sorts of the petitio principii. It is worth noticing that at the time of its foundation in 1866, the Paris Linguistic Society in 1866 banned the discussions of the origin of language. I shall pursue it anyhow.

  5. 5.

    In this and the following etymological presentations, I shall generally use: Klein, Ernest. 1971. A Comprehensive Etymological Dictionary of the English Language. Amsterdam: Elsevier; The Oxford English Dictionary 1989. 2nd ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press; Watkins, Calvert, ed., The American Heritage Dictionary of Indo-European Roots 2000. 2nd ed., Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co.; Barnhart, Robert K., ed. 1988. Barnhart Dictionary of Etymology. H.W. Wilson Co.; and especially the Online Etymology Dictionary 2001. New York: Douglas Harper.

  6. 6.

    In placing the metaphor in the center of epistemology, the opus of Hans Blumenberg stands out. Important translations are (Blumenberg 1996, 2010). One must also give credit to G. Lakoff and M. Johnson for having examined the relation between the development of a primitive vocabulary of the environment and the metaphorical function of language as a means to structure both our perception and understanding, as early as in the 1980s (Lakoff and Johnson 1980; Lakoff and Johnson 1999).

  7. 7.

    In classical Greek, the compound word “onomatopoeia” means “making or creating names.” Hence, they used a different word to refer to imitating sounds, namely “echomimesis.”

  8. 8.

    “theologia” is the same word in Greek and Latin.

  9. 9.

    Watkins, op. cit., p. 14.

References

  • Aristotle. 1994. Nicomachean Ethics. London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1990. Metaphysics. Book I-IX. London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenberg, Hans. 1996. Shipwreck with Spectator: Paradigm of a Metaphor for Existence. (trans: Steven Rendall). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenberg, Hans. 2010. Paradigms for a Metaphorology. Trans. Robert Savage. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, Ernst. 1923. Philosophie der symbolischen Formen. Berlin: Bruno Cassirer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, John. 2005. Art as experience. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epictetus. 1946/1995. The Discourses as reported by Arrian, the Manual, and Fragments. (With an English Translation by W.A. Oldfather). Cambridge: Loeb.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herder, Johann Gottfried. 2002. Philosophical Writings, Cambridge. (Contains full translations of How Philosophy, On the Origin, On the Cognition, and This Too, as well as other pieces). ed. Michael N. Forster, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, Hans. 1984/1979. The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of Ethics for the Technological Age (trans. of Das Prinzip Verantwortung) trans. Hans Jonas and David Herr. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1790/1974. Kritik der Urteilskraft. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 2003/1980. Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1999. Philosophy in the Flesh: the Embodied Mind and its Challenge to Western Thought. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirkeby, Ole F. 1994. Begivenhed og kropstanke. En fænomenologisk-hermeneutisk analyse. Aarhus: Modtryk.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirkeby, Ole F. 2010. The new protreptic. The concept and the art. Copenhagen: CBS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1690/1999. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. The Pennsylvania State University, Electronic Classics Series.The Pennsylvania State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maimonides, Moses. 2007. The Guide for the Perplexed. BN Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mey, Jacob. L. 1985. Whose language? A study in Linguistic Pragmatics. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1996a. Cratylus. London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1966b. Timaeus. London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, Paul. 1992. Oneself as another (trans. Kathleen Blamey). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, Calvert, ed. 2000. The American Heritage Dictionary of Indo-European Roots. 2nd ed. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ole Fogh Kirkeby .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kirkeby, O. (2016). Some Reflections on the Origin of Reason Through an Outline of the Genealogy of Language in the Light of Homonymity, Analogy, and Metaphor. In: Capone, A., Mey, J. (eds) Interdisciplinary Studies in Pragmatics, Culture and Society. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 4. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-12616-6_27

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-12616-6_27

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-12615-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-12616-6

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics