Skip to main content

Reconstructing Argumentative Discourse with the Help of Speech Act Conditions

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Interdisciplinary Studies in Pragmatics, Culture and Society

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 4))

Abstract

According to the pragma-dialectical approach to argumentation, for analysing argumentative discourse, a normative reconstruction is required which encompasses four kinds of transformations. It is explained in this chapter how speech act conditions can play a part in carrying out such a reconstruction. It is argued that integrating Searlean insights concerning speech acts with Gricean insights concerning conversational maxims can provide us with the necessary tools. For this, the standard theory of speech acts has to be amended in several respects and the conversational maxims have to be translated into speech act conditions. Making use of the rules of communication thus arrived at, and starting from the distribution of speech acts in a critical discussion as specified in the pragma-dialectical model, it is then demonstrated how indirect speech acts are to be transformed when reconstructing argumentative discourse. Finally, contextual clues for reconstruction found in argumentative activity types are discussed.

This chapter is based on van Eemeren and Grootendorst (Argumentation 3(4):367–383, 1989).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cf. van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1987).

  2. 2.

    Cf. van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1988).

  3. 3.

    The unstated parts of an argumentation can be referred to as “unexpressed premises”. Cf. van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984), pp. 119–149.

  4. 4.

    Of course, there can be other candidates: explanation, amplification, elucidation, but not argumentation.

  5. 5.

    Cf. van Eemeren and Grootendorst, where related views are also discussed (1984, pp. 33–39).

  6. 6.

    For practical purposes, we do not go into the exact relationship between sentences and propositions now. We just equate speech acts consisting of the expression of one proposition with one-sentence speech acts.

  7. 7.

    Cf. Searle's description of perlocutionary acts (1970, p. 25).

  8. 8.

    In practice, the difference of opinion can be expressed explicitly, but may also remain implicit, in which case the discussion or discursive text is based on the anticipation of a possible difference of opinion.

  9. 9.

    The rules are introduced and discussed in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984), pp. 51–175. A simplified non-technical version, specially adapted to the analysis of fallacies, is presented in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1987) and (1992).

  10. 10.

    Cf. Searle (1979), pp. 1–29.

  11. 11.

    The distribution of the various types of speech acts in the stages of a critical discussion is discussed in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984), pp. 95–118. Here, they also introduce the notion of language usage declaratives (1984, pp. 109–110).

  12. 12.

    The conversational maxims are introduced in Grice (1975), the rules for turn taking are discussed in Levinson (1983) and Edmondson (1981).

  13. 13.

    Of course this is a simplification, but it draws attention to the fact that proposing normative rules for critical discussion has more ties with reality than some people think. To give an example, one could refer to the similarities between the starting point in the ideal model that the participants in a critical discussion are striving for the resolution of a difference of opinion on the one hand, and the commonly accepted conversational fact that in ordinary conversation there is a preference for agreement among the interlocutors. As empirical research reported in van Eemeren et al. (2009) makes clear, the norms for reasonableness that are expressed in the rules for critical discussion are in fact to a large extent in agreement with those of ordinary arguers.

  14. 14.

    Cf. van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992).

  15. 15.

    In practice, of course, it is not at all uncommon for one of the rules of communication to be broken, but this does not necessarily mean that in such a case the Principle of Communication has been abandoned altogether. If this is the case, however, then the person doing so is reneging on a basic convention to which all the members of the community to which he belongs subscribe, and he or she thereby interferes with the communication. Assuming that it is not clear that a speaker is not in full control of his or her actions (he or she may be drunk for example), or cannot be held responsible for them, the speaker will have to account for this action or be faced with sanctions which may vary from an irritated reaction to a complete breaking off of the contact.

  16. 16.

    Cf. van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984), p. 41.

  17. 17.

    We call these operations dialectical transformations. Cf. van Eemeren (1986), (1987) and van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992). An approach which is in several respects akin to ours is developed in the many interesting articles of Jackson and Jacobs (e.g. 1980, 1981, 1982, 1983).

  18. 18.

    Unlike the resolution-centred reconstruction which takes place in a dialectical analysis, the transformations in the audience-centred reconstruction of a rhetorical analysis are motivated by a rhetorical ideal. However, a consistent apparatus for rhetorical analysis, providing us with all the necessary tools for transformation, is, in spite of the long-standing tradition of this form of analysis, not available.

  19. 19.

    A normative reconstruction in the dialectical sense represents a specific angle of approach which can be illuminating and, in the dialectical perspective, also the most appropriate. Naturally, other angles of approach are also possible. A psychological analysis, for instance, would undoubtedly be able to produce other interesting results. Things that appear as relevant from one angle remain out of sight when regarded from another. However, one angle of approach need not necessarily preclude another.

  20. 20.

    All elements of an analytical survey are of direct relevance to the evaluation of the argumentative discourse. If it is unclear what standpoint is being defended, there is no way of telling whether the argumentation that has been advanced is conclusive. And if more than one standpoint is being defended, it must be perfectly clear which language users are acting as the protagonist of which standpoint and exactly who is the source of the various argumentations that have been advanced in the defence of each standpoint. Otherwise, for example, it will be impossible to tell whether the various argumentations for the same standpoint actually constitute a coherent whole. Adequate evaluation of the argumentative discourse is also made more difficult where, as a result of implicitness or indirectness, arguments or unexpressed premises are overlooked or where it is unclear which argument schemes are relied on.

  21. 21.

    Cf. van Eemeren (1986, 1987).

  22. 22.

    Elsewhere, van Eemeren and Grootendorst have demonstrated this for the dialectical transformation of addition with regard to such implicit elements as unexpressed premises. Cf. van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1982, 1983, 1984, 1992).

  23. 23.

    For a distinction between four levels of context, see van Eemeren (2010), pp. 16–19.

  24. 24.

    Cf. van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992), pp. 56–59.

  25. 25.

    As a rule, every speech act presupposes its own acceptability. The Interaction Principle enables us to explain why speakers, even when the listener does not ask for it, take the effort to establish the acceptability of their speech acts by putting forward direct or indirect arguments. The interaction principle reflects in its formulation Sperber and Wilson's principle of relevance: “Every act of ostensive communication communicates the presumption of its own optimal relevance” (1986, p. 158). There are important differences, however. Firstly, the interaction principle is more general than the principle of relevance—even if relevance is taken in its broadest sense—and, secondly, it is formulated in terms of speech act theory, whereas Sperber and Wilson make it their business to reject speech act theory completely (1986, pp. 243–254).

  26. 26.

    The sentence in parentheses refers to the unexpressed premise in the argumentation.

  27. 27.

    Cf. van Eemeren (1986).

  28. 28.

    As a matter of fact, one of Austin’s reasons for developing a theory of speech acts refers to the logical positivists simplistic dichotomy between truth-functional statements and non-truth-functional statements. According to Austin, performative utterances are both non-truth functional and non-metaphysical.

References

  • Edmondson, W. 1981. Spoken discourse. A model for analysis. London: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. 1975. Logic and conversation. In Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts, eds. P. Cole and J. L. Morgan, 43-58. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, S., and S. Jacobs. 1980. Structure of conversational argument: Pragmatic bases for the enthymeme. The Quarterly Journal of Speech 66:251–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, S., and S. Jacobs. 1981. The collaborative production of proposals in conversational argument and persuasion: A study of disagreement regulation. Journal of the American Forensic Association 18:77–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, S., and S. Jacobs. 1982. Conversational argument: A discourse analytic approach. In Advances in argumentation theory and research, eds. J. R. Cox and Ch. A. Willard, 205–237. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, S., and S. Jacobs. 1983. Speech acts’ structure in conversation. Rational aspects of pragmatic coherence. In Conversational coherence: Form, structure, and strategy, eds. R. T. Craig and K, Tracy, 47–66. Beverly Hills: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. 1983. Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poppel, L. van. 2013. Getting the vaccine now will protect you in the future! A pragma-dialectical analysis of strategic manoeuvering with pragmatic argumentation in health brochures. Doctoral dissertation. University of Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. 1970. Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. 1979. Expression and meaning: Studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., and D. Wilson. 1986. Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. 1986. Dialectical analysis as a normative reconstruction of argumentative discourse. Text 6 (1): 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. 1987. Argumentation studies' five estates. In Argument and critical practices. Proceedings of the fifth SCA/AFA Conference on Argumentation, ed. J. W. Wenzel, 9–24. Annandale: Speech Communication Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. 2010. Strategic maneuvering in argumentative discourse. Extending the pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., B. Garssen, and B. Meuffels. 2009. Fallacies and judgments of reasonableness. Empirical research concerning the pragma-dialectical discussion rules. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., and R. Grootendorst. 1982. Unexpressed premisses: Part I. Journal of the American Forensic Association 19:97–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., and R. Grootendorst. 1983. Unexpressed premisses: Part II. Journal of the American Forensic Association 19:215–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., and R. Grootendorst. 1984. Speech acts in argumentative discussions. A theoretical model for the analysis of discussions. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., and R. Grootendorst. 1987. Fallacies in pragma-dialectical perspective. Argumentation 1 (3): 283–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., and R. Grootendorst. 1988. Rationale for a pragma-dialectical perspective. Argumentation 2 (2): 271–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., and R. Grootendorst. 1989. Speech act conditions as tools for reconstructing argumentative discourse. Argumentation 3 (4): 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., and R. Grootendorst. 1992. Argumentation, communication, and fallacies. A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frans H. van Eemeren .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

van Eemeren, F., Garssen, B. (2016). Reconstructing Argumentative Discourse with the Help of Speech Act Conditions. In: Capone, A., Mey, J. (eds) Interdisciplinary Studies in Pragmatics, Culture and Society. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 4. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-12616-6_17

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-12616-6_17

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-12615-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-12616-6

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics