Skip to main content

Musical Autonomy and Musical Meaning: A Historical Overview

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Teaching Performance: A Philosophy of Piano Pedagogy

Part of the book series: Contemporary Philosophies and Theories in Education ((COPT,volume 7))

  • 1278 Accesses

Abstract

The nineteenth century gave birth to the idea of absolute music—(mainly) instrumental music that, due to its lack of mimetic effects and its pure, immaterial form, was thought to transcend the non-musical world and expose its essences; it was thought to forge a more profound connection to the world than could art forms allied with language. This chapter surveys classic formulations of this idea by Schelling, E. T. A. Hoffman, and other German intellectuals. Especially useful will be Schopenhauer’s (and Susanne Langer’s) notion that music is a symbol not primarily of particular emotions but of the dynamics of experience that underlie various emotions.This chapter also locates a precedent of absolute music in Kantian thought and an heir to it in Adorno.

Art is autonomous and it is not.

—Theodor Adorno, Aesthetic Theory

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Gombrich 1951. Goodman (1976, p. 5) similarly argues that representation does not depend on resemblance but is purely a symbolic (denotative) relation.

  2. 2.

    Giorgio Vasari, a biographer of Michelangelo, marvels at the realism of the artist’s sculpture Pietà—of every muscle, vein, and limb—but then goes on to state that Michelangelo has produced “such perfection as Nature can but rarely produce in the flesh” (his italics). Lives of the Most Eminent Painters, Sculptors, and Architects; quoted in Treitler 1989, pp. 67–68. As for the novel, another supposed mimetic artform par excellence, Wolfgang Iser has argued that it is not realistic but rather comprises the frame by which we configure reality. It represents, if anything, the faculty of memory, by which we make sense of reality, bringing order to multiplicity. “The traditional realistic novel can no longer be regarded as a mirror-reflection of reality, but is, rather, a paradigm of the structure of memory…” (1978, p. 125). More simply, fiction “must always in some way transcend the world to which it refers” (ibid., 182).

  3. 3.

    See Subotnik’s critique of empirical, Anglo-American musicology in 1991, pp. 3–14.

  4. 4.

    I simplify here for the sake of exposition; topoi almost always operate in tandem, thus generating more complex meanings than any one topic could on its own.

  5. 5.

    Allanbrook 1983, p. 6 (my italics). A similar and very common phenomenon in the Classical period (and to some extent in other styles as well) is that of one instrument imitating another, as when the piano imitates the voice or orchestra, and of one genre imitating another, as when the solo sonata imitates a concerto through virtuosic passagework (usually in approaching a major formal juncture). Also regarding concerto, Charles Rosen notes that “mimesis of the tutti-solo alternation is standard throughout late eighteenth century music of whatever genre” (1988, p. 77). Here again, such music-to-music reference connotes emotional states—the evocation of concerto in a sonata, for instance, generates no small amount of anticipation and excitement—but such paramusical reference is conspicuously mediated by intra-musical reference.

  6. 6.

    Kant 1790, p. 104. Imagination grasps a manifold while understanding unifies it.

  7. 7.

    For this reason, Peter de Bolla (2002, p. 27) characterizes reflective judgments as “radically subjective”— the universal follows from the individual judgment rather than the reverse.

  8. 8.

    Kant 1790, p. 57.

  9. 9.

    I have provided barely a thumbnail sketch of Kant’s aesthetics—only as much as was needed for our present purposes. For an extensive exegesis, see Guyer 1997.

  10. 10.

    I should clarify that Kant’s actual views on music (as laid out in Sects. 53 and 54 of the Third Critique) are cursory and notoriously deficient. Briefly, he considered music incapable of stimulating the free play of cognition and thus incapable of being an object of beauty. (Peter Kivy attributes this verdict to Kant’s lack of familiarity with Classical form and syntax; see Kivy’s 1993 commentary on the suggestive yet ultimately unsuccessful elements of Kant’s musical theory.) In what follows, I shall extrapolate from Kant’s general theory a more charitable and promising Kantian view of music than he himself allowed.

  11. 11.

    See Bonds 1991.

  12. 12.

    However, as Dahlhaus (1991, p. 163 ff.) reminds us, musical logic does not depend exclusively upon linear, causal relations. For, on the one hand, not all contiguous events are processive (“not everything that ‘proceeds’… is a ‘process’”), and on the other, non-contiguous events may be related—sometimes music evinces non-linear logic.

  13. 13.

    Schenker 1910, p. 291 (his italics). Interestingly, though Schenker employs an organicist metaphor here, and in later work fervently espouses organicist ideology overall, here he emphasizes that such causality is fabricated rather than real: “the artistic instinct discovered in the compulsion to prepare and resolve a dissonance a most welcome means of feigning a kind of musical causality and necessity at least from harmony to harmony (ibid., 291, first italics his, second mine). In fact, in an earlier writing, “The Spirit of Musical Technique” (Schenker 1895), he holds music to be essentially inorganic.

  14. 14.

    Subotnik 1991, p. 196. However, Subotnik continues with the caveat that one cannot assume such musical reason to be absolute and invariant, for even “pure” musical logic needs to be interpreted by humans who introduce elements external to such logic. Classical music as a self-explanatory mechanism, then, is at once universal and contingent, somewhat dependent on the systems of meaning people apply to music.

  15. 15.

    Ibid.

  16. 16.

    “Even in cases where the composer himself has employed pictorial tags in talking about his work—calling one symphony ‘Pastoral,’ one movement ‘Brook Scene’ and another ‘Jolly Concourse of Peasants’—these tropes are properly reducible to purely musical elements rather than standing for actual objects expressed through music” (Nietzsche 1871, p. 44).

  17. 17.

    This duplicitous aspect of the aesthetic is nicely captured by Henry Kingsbury’s recollection of a studio teacher who counseled his students to abide by the letter and law of the score but somehow convinced them that this is what they subjectively preferred. “A fundamental principle of Goldmann’s teaching was that students must play what is printed in the score, and yet that they must not play something simply because it is written in the score, but rather because they feel it that way” (Kingsbury 1988, p. 87, my italics). I return to the politics of interpretation in the next chapter.

  18. 18.

    Of course, one must be careful not to overgeneralize, for some eighteenth-century writers were skeptical of musical mimesis, or qualified it in some respect. Christoph Koch, for example, writing in 1802, states,

    Some… similarities exist between natural phenomena and musical tones and one can transfer them to music; but music betrays its nature when it takes over such descriptions, since its one and only object is to depict the feelings of the heart, and not the picture of inanimate things. Most devices for tone painting are objectionable… since they divert the attention from the principal content to accessory things (Musikalisches Lexikon, p. 924. Quoted in Ratner 1980, p. 25).

    For another example, Johann Sulzer, while condoning mimesis and the evocation of affects (in all of the fine arts, including music), deems it necessary that these arts capture not merely the sensuous form of a phenomenon but also its inner essence. Correlatively, he eschewed artistic perception weighed too heavily toward the sensory; rather, the perceiver need also register her own inner sense of the artwork, “where attention is directed from the object itself to what the soul is feeling…. In this way, one’s mind loses sight of the object itself, and feels all the more its animated effects. The soul becomes, in essence, all feeling; it knows of nothing outside, but only of what is inside itself” (1774, p. 33). What begins as attention to the sensory, mimetic qualities of an artwork eventuates in self-reflection and self-absorption, such that the perceiver grasps something essential not only about the depicted object but also about her own emotional sensibility.

  19. 19.

    Ibid., 146. Also see Hoffman 1813.

  20. 20.

    Treitler 1989, p. 177. See Carl Dahlhaus’s seminal study, The Idea of Absolute Music, especially Chap. 3, for more on the evolution of this idea.

  21. 21.

    Translated taken from by Bonds 1997, p. 403. Also, Ian Biddle states that music, for Schelling, evokes “the externality of the universe without violating the boundaries of its own ontology” (1996, p. 35).

  22. 22.

    I use the 8th edition from 1891, page numbers from which will be cited in the text.

  23. 23.

    I adopt the next two paragraphs from Swinkin 2013, p. 101.

  24. 24.

    Busoni expresses an almost identical sentiment: music “set[s] in vibration our human moods…. But not the moving cause itself of those spiritual affections;—not the joy over an avoided danger…. an emotional state, yes, but not the psychic species of this emotion…. Is it possible to imagine how a poor but contented man could be represented by music? The contentment, the soul-state, can be interpreted by music; but where does the poverty appear…? (1911, p. 13). For a more recent argument along these lines, see Robinson 1987, which holds that music can describe an object but not depict it; it can posit a predicate but not a subject.

  25. 25.

    While I subscribe to musical form embodying generalized dynamics of sentient experience, I do not deem that incompatible with music’s ability to embody particular feelings. I pursue this idea later on, and also refer you to Swinkin 2013.

  26. 26.

    Schopenhauer 1818–1819; translation taken from Le Huray and Day 1981, p. 329 (my italics). (See Budd 1985, pp. 76–103 for a critique of some of these principles.) Nascent ideas regarding the essentialist function of art can be traced back to British aesthetics in the eighteenth century. Sir Joshua Reynolds, for example, as discussed by James Sambrook, likens the painter to the “philosophic naturalist who determines the general form of a species from the minute examination of many specimens” (Sambrook 1993, p. 151). Art shares with the natural sciences the capacity to abstract from and generalize about natural phenomena; this capacity was considered superior to merely replicating contingent features.

  27. 27.

    Meyer 1956 also subscribes to the view that aesthetic affect is undifferentiated.

  28. 28.

    Before proceeding, a caveat is in order. In the above, very brief survey of the notion of absolute music, I have perhaps committed an error of which Sanna Pederson accuses Dahlhaus: glossing over differences among various thinkers’ use of the concept, implying that it was used more uniformly or consistently in the course of its history than it really was. While my survey is less nuanced than Pederson’s account, it is adequate for our present purposes. Also, Pederson takes issue with Dahlhaus’s assertion that Hanslick, in claiming that instrumental music epitomized pure, “tonally moving” forms, implied that such music enjoyed metaphysical status. On the contrary, Pederson claims: Hanslick deliberately omitted references to absolute music in all editions of On the Musically Beautiful subsequent to the first, precisely because he wanted to uphold a notion of pure form that possessed no other, extra-musical intimations (Pederson 2009, pp. 251–253). Yet, I think Hanslick’s initial commitment to the idea of absolute music is not entirely negated by his subsequent expurgations.

  29. 29.

    Cookpoints out that the categories in which musical phenomena are placed are contingent: what is considered a work in one time, place, or culture might be considered a piece in another; what is considered an instance of a work (a token) in one might be considered a work (a type) in another. However, he cautions, the musical work is not only a social construction, for “underlying any such categorization is some kind of material trace… which may, or may not, afford a given interpretation” (Cook 1999, p. 203).

  30. 30.

    Bojan Bujic states that while notation was originally an aide-mémoire, it subsequently became emancipated from this function, and “the whole subsequent course of Western notation represents a move away from memory towards the state in which a written document can stand on its own… representing the musical work” (Bujic 1993, p. 134). Cf. Adorno 2006, p. 71, where he disputes the notion that musical notation was ever an aid to memory.

  31. 31.

    Marx 1859 (translation taken from Burnham 1997, p. 159, fn. 2).

  32. 32.

    Likewise, as Erinn Knyt explains, Busoni holds that music

    could be shaped in response to a human idea drawn from the composer’s psyche or surroundings. This is probably one of the most original aspects of his notion of the absolute in music. He idealized forms constructed in relation to cultural ideas rather than genres…. Busoni’s Ideen were unlike explicit programmes in that they provided the impetus for musical concepts that influenced texture, structures [and so on] without providing any narrative or explicit images. Yet they were also not specifically musical. They had to be translated into an abstract musical idea, an Einfall, that then had to receive concrete forms in tones and rhythms (Knyt 2012, p. 46).

  33. 33.

    Rumph 2005 discusses this epigraph

  34. 34.

    Nietzsche expresses a similar sentiment: “The poet cannot tell us anything that was not already contained, with a most universal validity, in such music as prompted him to his figurative discourse. The cosmic symbolism of music resists any adequate treatment by language, for the simple reason that music, in referring to primordial contradiction and pain, symbolizes a sphere which is both earlier than appearance and beyond it. Once we set it over against music, all appearance becomes a mere analogy” (1871, p. 46, my italics).

  35. 35.

    On a similar note, Reynolds 1988 argues that in An die Ferne Geliebte, Beethoven ingeniously portrays the basic dynamic of separation–integration as alluded to by the text within purely musical terms, through a process of motivic integration. That is, motives that were initially separate (texturally and temporally) are later, in the sixth song, amalgamated; the motivic process encodes the initial alienation and subsequent rapprochement of the two lovers. Yet, Reynolds is careful to emphasize that, although Beethoven’s music does indeed represent this “underlying idea of action… Beethoven’s representational approach goes beyond mimesis and thus cannot be considered programmatic” (1988, p. 193). That is, the motion-schema embedded in the music does not merely serve to depict the text but also to engender intrinsic musical sense—an immanent structural process— and, along with that, to express a universal dynamic of experience that transcends the more particular circumstance depicted by the text.

  36. 36.

    Adorno 1962, p. 75. Deleuze and Guattari would likely disagree with the last clause, as they detect in Wagner’s leitmotif technique a vehicle for musical autonomy: as an opera unfolds, leitmotifs “increasingly enter into conjunction… become autonomous from the dramatic action… and independent of characters and landscapes; they themselves become melodic landscapes” (1987, p. 319). Likewise, Schoenberg 1932 eschews text painting and professes to use “representational words”—words that would seem to require such painting—as he would any other word: to enhance musical structure, to further “the immediate, vivid rendering of the whole and of its parts” (32). Schoenberg, in turn, cites a precedent for this approach in Schubert, who, in a desire to compose a “comprehensive melody… may pass over a salient textual feature…. a genuine melody will arise relatively seldom from a procedure which strongly emphasizes the text” (41).

  37. 37.

    Langer 1953, p. 153 (her italics). Langer terms this phenomenon the “principle of assimilation.”

  38. 38.

    Even Schenker asserts that “seldom do the masters create a work of significance without some definable impetus from the outside world,” and affirms that programmatic content and musical form are thoroughly compatible (1905–1909, p. 52).

  39. 39.

    Hegel 1820–1829, p. 46. Treitler (1989, p. 211) makes a similar point regarding Mozart: his instrumental music does not render concrete scenarios (of the sort found in his operas) more psychologically complex; rather, his operatic music renders psychological complexity (of the sort found in his instrumental music) more concrete—it frames the abstract psychical patterns embodied in symphonies and sonatas by particular circumstances.

  40. 40.

    For a well-known example, see Reti’s (1951, pp. 31–55) analysis of Schumann’s Kinderszenen; for a lesser-known example, see Brodbeck’s (1986) analysis of Schubert’s Ländler, op. 171. For a more general discussion of unity within cyclic compositions, see Neumeyer 1997.

  41. 41.

    Schenker 1926 speaks to this point, noting that Chopin’s Waltz in A-flat, op. 34, no. 1 actually consists of “three short waltzes” that are connected by means of a large arpeggiation. “What appears to be a loose assemblage in the manner of a potpourri reveals itself… to be a tightly organized whole” (7).

  42. 42.

    Also see Hatten 2004 , Chap. 8 where he discusses the motivic import of resonance and articulation in Schubert’s posthumous A major Piano Sonata, and Littlewood 2004, where he points out that in Brahms’s op. 9, the portato articulation becomes “a motivic idea in itself, independent of its one-time patron, repeated notes” (263).

  43. 43.

    Leistra-Jones 2013 expertly traces these two divergent and largely coextensive paths in nineteenth- century performance culture, in which Brahms and Joachim epitomized performative sincerity and authenticity, Liszt theatricality and self-display. However, the former, Leistra-Jones argues, is no less a self-conscious mode of performing than is the latter; Joachim, in particular, ‘performed’ authenticity—’performed’, that is, a supposed lack of performativity!

  44. 44.

    By analogy, Hans-Georg Gadamer asserts that “changing the established forms is no less a kind of connection with the tradition than defending the established forms,” “Replik,” cited in Hoy 1978, p. 127.

  45. 45.

    Cone 1986. Page numbers will be cited in text.

  46. 46.

    Just as, according to Adorno, there is no pure form, Cone implies there is no purely objective analysis: the analyst’s understanding and formulation of ostensibly purely music-structural relations will necessarily be conditioned by the non-musical experiences to which the analyst can relate, and that he thinks resonates with the piece. More on this presently; also see Guck 1998.

  47. 47.

    Similar narratives have been adduced of Schubert’s posthumous B-flat piano sonata (Fisk 1997) and of Mozart’s Symphony No. 40, second movement (Guck 1994). In fact, we might deem my reading an instance of a veritable musical-narrative archetype. Incidentally, Cone’s analysis could also perhaps be construed in terms of a psychological scenario: (1) one undergoes (or recalls having undergone) a problematic or anomalous experience and its resultant feeling (measure 12); (2) these are repressed (measure 13); (3) because the repression is not entirely successful, the repressed returns in other forms (measure 16); (4) the problematic feeling seems to be resolved or understood (measure 47); (5) this resolution turns out to be innocuous or even illusory—the repressed feeling is much more complex and problematic than initially thought, and thus recurs in intensified form, as an emotional outburst or neurotic symptom (measure 65).

  48. 48.

    For a dense theoretical exposition of music as social homology, see Shepherd and Wicke 1997.

  49. 49.

    See Burnham 1989.

References

  • Adorno, Theodor W. 1962. Introduction to the sociology of music. Trans. E. B. Ashton. New York: Continuum (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, Theodor W. 1997. Aesthetic theory, ed. Robert Hullot-Kentor. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, Theodor W. 2006. Towards a theory of musical reproduction (notes and draft). Trans. Wieland Hoban. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allanbrook, Wye Jamison. 1983. Rhythmic gesture in Mozart: Le Nozze Di Figaro and Don Giovanni. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berger, Karol. 2000. A theory of art. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biddle, Ian. 1996. F. W. J. Schelling’s Philosophie der Kunst: An emergent semiology of music. In Music theory in the age of romanticism, ed. Ian Bent, 25–36. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonds, Mark Evans. 1991. Wordless rhetoric: Musical form and the metaphor of the oration. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bonds, Mark Evans. 1997. Idealism and the aesthetics of instrumental music at the turn of the nineteenth century. Journal of the American Musicological Society 50 (2–3): 387–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brodbeck, David. 1986. Dance music as high art: Schubert’s Twelve Ländler, op. 171 (D. 790). In Schubert: Critical and analytical studies, ed. Walter Frisch, 31–47. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Budd, Malcolm. 1985. Music and the emotions: The philosophical theories. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bujic, Bojan. 1993. Notation and realization: Musical performance in historical perspective. In The interpretation of music: Philosophical essays, ed. Michael Krausz, 129–40. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnham, Scott. 1989. The role of sonata form in A. B. Marx’s theory of form. Journal of Music Theory 33 (2): 247–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnham, Scott. 1997. Ed. and trans. A. B. Marx, Musical form in the age of Beethoven: Selected writings on theory and method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Busoni, Ferruccio. 1911. Sketch of a new aesthetic of music. Trans. Theodore Baker. New York: Dover (1962).

    Google Scholar 

  • Cone, Edward T. 1974. The composer’s voice. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cone, Edward T. 1986. Schubert’s promissory note: An exercise in musical hermeneutics. In Schubert: Critical and analytical studies, ed. Walter Frisch, 13–30. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cone, Edward T. 1992. Poet’s love or composer’s love? In Music and text: Critical inquiries, ed. Steven P. Scher, 177–92. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cook, Nicholas. 1999. At the border of musical identity: Schenker, Corelli and the Graces. Music Analysis 18 (2): 179–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dahlhaus, Carl. 1989. The idea of absolute music. Trans. Roger Lustig. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahlhaus, Carl. 1991. Ludwig van Beethoven: Approaches to his music. Trans. Mary Whittall. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Bolla, Peter. 2002. Toward the materiality of aesthetic experience. Diacritics 32 (1): 19–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles, and Felix Guattari. 1987. A thousand plateaus, vol. II of Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Trans. Brian Massumi, 3–25. Minneapolis: University of Minneapolis Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eagleton, Terry. 1990. The ideology of the aesthetic. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, David. 1979. Beyond orpheus: Studies in musical structure. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisk, Charles. 1997. What Schubert’s last sonata might hold. In Music and meaning, ed. Jenefer Robinson, 179–200. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goehr, Lydia. 1992. The imaginary museum of musical works: An essay in the philosophy of music. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goehr, Lydia. 1993. Music has no meaning to speak of: On the politics of musical interpretation. In The interpretation of music, ed. Michael Krausz, 277–90. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gombrich, Ernst H. 1951. Meditations on a hobby horse. In Aspects of form: A symposium on form in nature and art, ed. Lancelot Whyte. London: Lund Humphries.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Nelson. 1976. Languages of art: An approach to a theory of symbols. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guck, Marion. 1994. Rehabilitating the incorrigible. In Theory, analysis and meaning in music, ed. Anthony Pople, 57–73. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guck, Marion. 1998. Analytical fictions. In Music/ideology: Resisting the aesthetic, ed. Adam Krims, 157–78. Amsterdam: G and B Arts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, Paul. 1997. Kant and the claims of taste. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanslick, Eduard. 1891. On the musically beautiful: A contribution towards the revision of the aesthetics of music. Trans. Geoffrey Payzant, from the 8th edition of Vom Musikalisch-Schönen. Indianapolis: Hackett (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatten, Robert. 2004. Interpreting musical gestures, topics, and tropes: Mozart, Beethoven, Schubert. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, Georg W. F. 1820–1829. Introductory lectures on aesthetics. Trans. Bernard Bosanquet. London: Penguin (1993).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, E. T. A. 1810. Review of Beethoven’s fifth symphony. In Music analysis in the nineteenth century, vol. II. Trans. Martyn Clarke, David Charlton and Ian Bent, 141–60. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (1994).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, E. T. A. 1813. Beethoven’s instrumental music. Trans. Oliver Strunk. In Writings of german composers, eds. Jost Hermand and James Steakley, 89–93. New York: Continuun (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoy, David Couzens. 1978. The critical circle: Literature, history, and philosophical hermeneutics. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iser, Wolfgang. 1978. The act of reading: A theory of aesthetic response. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1790. Critique of the power of judgment. Trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (2000).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingsbury, Henry. 1988. Music, talent, and performance: A conservatory cultural system. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kivy, Peter. 1993. Kant and the Affektenlehre: What he said, and what I wish he had said. In The fine art of repetition: Essays in the philosophy of music, 250–64. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knyt, Erinn E. 2012. Ferruccio Busoni and the absolute in music: Form, nature and Idee. Journal of the Royal Musical Association 137 (1): 35–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsyn, Kevin. 2003. Decentering music: A critique of contemporary musical research. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kunze, Stephan. 1972. Die ‘wirklich gantz neue Manier’ in Beethovens eroica-variationen op. 35. Archiv für Musikwissenschaft 29:124–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langer, Susanne K. 1953. Feeling and form. New York: Charles Scribner and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langer, Susanne K. 1957. Philosophy in a new key: A study in the symbolism of reason, rite, and art, 3rd edition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Huray, Peter, and James Day. eds. 1981. Music and aesthetics in the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leistra-Jones, Karen. 2013. Staging authenticity: Joachim, Brahms, and the politics of Werktreue performance. Journal of the American Musicological Society 66 (2): 397–436.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, Edward. 1970. Compositional technique and musical expressivity. Journal of Research in Music Education 18 (1): 3–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Littlewood, Julian. 2004. The variations of Johannes Brahms. London: Plumbago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mark, Thomas Carson. 1981. Philosophy of piano playing: Reflections on the concept of performance. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 41 (3): 299–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marx, A. B. 1859. Musical form in the age of Beethoven: Selected writings on theory and method. ed. and trans. Scott Burnham. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, Leonard. 1956. Emotion and meaning in music. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neumeyer, David. 1997. Synthesis and association, structure and design in multi-movement compositions. In Music theory in concept and practice, eds. David Beach et al., 197–216. Rochester: University of Rochester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newcomb, Anthony. 1984. Sound and feeling. Critical Inquiry 10:614–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1871. The birth of tragedy. Trans. Francis Golffing. New York: Doubleday (1956).

    Google Scholar 

  • Paddison, Max. 1993. Adorno’s aesthetics of music. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pederson, Sanna. 2009. Defining the term ‘Absolute Music’ historically. Music and Letters 90 (2): 240–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratner, Leonard G. 1980. Classic music: Expression, form, and style. New York: Schirmer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reti, Rudolph. 1951. The thematic process in music. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, Christopher. 1988a. The representational impulse in Late Beethoven I: An die ferne Geliebte. Acta Musicologica 60 (1): 43–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, Christopher. 1988b. The representational impulse in Late Beethoven II: String quartet in F Major, op. 135. Acta Musicologica 60 (2): 180–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, Jenefer. 1987. Music as a representational art. In What is music? An introduction to the philosophy of music, ed. Philip Alperson, 165–92. University Park: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, Charles. 1988. Sonata forms. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumph, Stephen. 2005. Beethoven and the Ut Pictura Poësis tradition. Beethoven Forum 12 (2): 113–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sambrook, James. 1993. The eighteenth century: The intellectual and cultural context of English literature, 1700–89. New York: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samson, Jim. 2000. The practice of early-nineteenth-century pianism. In The musical work: Reality or invention? Ed. Michael Talbot, 110–27. Liverpool: Liverpool University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schenker, Heinrich. 1895. The spirit of musical technique. Appendix to Nicholas Cook, The Schenker project: Race, culture, and music theory in fin-de-siècle Vienna, 319–32. Trans. William Pastille. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schenker, Heinrich. 1905–1909 (circa). The decline of the art of composition: A technical-critical study. Trans. William Drabkin. Music Analysis 24 (1–2) (2005): 32–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schenker, Heinrich. 1910. Counterpoint, book I. Trans. John Rothgeb and Jürgen Thym. Ann Arbor: Musicalia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schenker, Heinrich. 1926. Further consideration of the Urlinie: II. In The masterwork in music: A yearbook, vol. 2, 1–22. Trans. John Rothgeb. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, John, and Peter Wicke. 1997. Music and cultural theory. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiller, Friedrich. 1795. On the aesthetic education of man. Trans. Reginald Snell. Mineola: ­Dover (2004).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoenberg, Arnold. 1932. Analysis of the four orchestral songs op. 22. In Perspectives on Schoenberg and Stravinsky, ed. Benjamin Boretz and Edward T. Cone, 25–46. Trans. Claudio Spies. Princeton: Princeton University Press (1968).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, Arthur. 1818–1819. The world as will and representation. Trans. E. F. J. Payne, vol. I. New York: Dover (1966).

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, John, and Peter Wicke. 1997. Music and cultural theory. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Subotnik, Rose Rosengard. 1991. Developing variations: Style and ideology in Western music. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sulzer, Johann Georg. 1774. General theory of the fine arts. Excerpts reprinted in Aesthetics and the art of musical composition in the German enlightenment: Selected writings of Johann Georg Sulzer and Heinrich Christoph Koch, eds. and Trans. Nancy Kovaleff Baker and Thomas Christensen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (1995).

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinkin, Jeffrey. 2013. An account of emotional specificity in classic-romantic music. Current Musicology 94:97–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treitler, Leo. 1989. Music and the historical imagination. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Kendall L. 1990. Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeffrey Swinkin .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Swinkin, J. (2015). Musical Autonomy and Musical Meaning: A Historical Overview. In: Teaching Performance: A Philosophy of Piano Pedagogy. Contemporary Philosophies and Theories in Education, vol 7. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-12514-5_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics