Skip to main content

Loss Aversion, Omission Bias and the Civil Standard of Proof

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
European Perspectives on Behavioural Law and Economics

Part of the book series: Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship ((EALELS,volume 2))

Abstract

This article shows how insights from cognitive psychology, namely loss aversion, omission bias and status quo bias, explain the intuitive appeal of a standard of proof in civil cases that is considerably higher than the “preponderance of the evidence” or “balance of probabilities” standard employed by Common Law. These insights may explain the almost visceral rejection any suggestions lowering the standard of proof in civil matters have received in Germany. They do not, however, provide a normative basis for a standard of proof higher than 50 % posterior subjective probability in civil cases.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Addington vs. Texas, 441 U.S. 418 (1979), 422, 423; for English law In Re H & Others (minors) UKHL 16, AC 563 (1995), sect. 76; Wright 2009, 80.

  2. 2.

    Engel 2009, 435; Motsch 2009, 242.

  3. 3.

    Paulus 1997, 750; Kokott 1998, 18; Clermont and Sherwin 2002, 262 et seq.; Engel 2009, 435; Motsch 2009, 242; but see Gottwald 2000, 175; Brinkmann 2005, 3.

  4. 4.

    For US law O’Malley et al. 2001, § 166.51; for English law Miller vs. Minister of Pensions , 3 All ER 372 (1947), 373 et seq.

  5. 5.

    For English law Redmayne 1999, 172; for US law Livanovitch v. Livanovitch, 131 A. 799, 800 (Vt. 1926) (“If […] you are more inclined to believe from the evidence that he did so deliver the bonds to the defendant, even though your belief is only the slightest degree greater than that he did not, your verdict should be for the plaintiff” (quoting the jury instructions).

  6. 6.

    The standard of proof in Germany is better described as a “conviction raisonnée” rather than the French “conviction intime ”; see Deppenkemper 2004, 208 et seq., 421 and the references cited therein.

  7. 7.

    BGHZ 53, 245 = BGH NJW 1970, 946 (translation from German by the author); for Swiss law BGE 130 III 321 sect. 3.2.

  8. 8.

    For German law Kadner Graziano 2011, 189; for Swiss law Berger-Steiner 2008, sect. 6.81; Walter 2009, 53; Bühler 2010, sect. 9.

  9. 9.

    For German law Greger 1978, 110; for Swiss law Summermatter and Jacober 2012, 142.

  10. 10.

    For German law Bender 1981, 258; Fuchs 2005, 80.

  11. 11.

    See, e.g., for German law BGH NJW 1995, 2169; NJW 2004, 777; for Swiss law BGE 130 III 321 sect. 3.3; 132 III 715 sect. 3.2.

  12. 12.

    Walter 1979, 184.

  13. 13.

    But see Gottwald 2000, 175; Brinkmann 2005, 3, who argue against any difference in principle between the German and the Common Law’s standard of proof in civil cases.

  14. 14.

    Prütting 2010, 142.

  15. 15.

    Clermont and Sherwin 2002, 244.

  16. 16.

    The seminal papers are Kaplan 1968 and Cullison 1969.

  17. 17.

    The use of the plural for “statements” is deliberate. In my view, the Bayesian posterior probability must be for the joint probability of all relevant factual statements being true. This avoids the much debated “conjunction paradox” at the potential cost of defining standard of proof differently than current law.

  18. 18.

    Kegel 1967, 337; Maassen 1975, 10; Redmayne 1999, 172; Posner 2007, 647, but see Motsch 1983, 83.

  19. 19.

    See Park et al. 2010, for an overview. The debate started with Finkelstein and Fairley 1970 and the answer came from Tribe 1971. The collection of essays by Tillers 1988 provides an overview of the debate up to that time, and Tillers 2011 a summary of the debate since.

  20. 20.

    See the references cited in Tillers and Gottfried 2007.

  21. 21.

    Rosenberg 1965, 16.

  22. 22.

    Baumgärtel 1996, n. 9.

  23. 23.

    Musielak 1975, 49.

  24. 24.

    Kaye 1987, 55.

  25. 25.

    Biemann 2009, 207.

  26. 26.

    Bourmistrov-Jüttner 1987, 247.

  27. 27.

    Cullison 1969, 564 et seqq.; DeKay 1996, 111.

  28. 28.

    Kaplan 1968, 1072.

  29. 29.

    In US law, a further intermediate standard of proof known as “clear and convincing evidence”, which is applicable in certain civil cases (e.g., civil fraud), is well-established, see, e.g., Addington vs. Texas, 441 U.S. 418 (1979), 422, 423, while it is a matter of controversy whether English law recognizes such an intermediate standard of proof, Anderson et al. 2006, 243; McBride 2009, 325 et seq.

  30. 30.

    See Addington vs. Texas, 441 U.S. 418 (1979), 422, 423; for English law In Re H & Others (minors) UKHL 16, AC 563 (1995), sect. 76; Wright 2009, 80.

  31. 31.

    Jury instructions according to the Ninth Circuit Model Criminal Jury Instructions, 2003 edition, § 3.5– Reasonable Doubt—Defined. Sheppard 2003 shows the development from “moral certainty” to “reasonable doubt” to “articulate doubt”, which, according to him, explains the current practice in criminal law better.

  32. 32.

    O’Malley et al. 2001, § 166.51.

  33. 33.

    Livanovitch v. Livanovitch, 131 A. 799, 800 (Vt. 1926) (“If […] you are more inclined to believe from the evidence that he did so deliver the bonds to the defendant, even though your belief is only the slightest degree greater than that he did not, your verdict should be for the plaintiff” (quoting the jury instructions); Pennsylvania Suggested Standard Civil Jury Instructions, 3rd ed. 2005, § 1.42; for English law Redmayne 1999, 172.

  34. 34.

    Illinois Supreme Court Committee on Pattern Jury Instructions in Civil Cases (eds.), Illinois Pattern Jury Instructions: Civil, § 21.01 (“more probably true than not true”), available from www.state.il.us/court/CircuitCourt/CivilJuryInstructions/21.00.pdf (last visited 1 August 2012); Sand et al. 2007, Vol. 4, § 73.01, Instruction 73–2 (“by a preponderance of the evidence” means “more likely true than not true”).

  35. 35.

    See the references cited in Tillers and Gottfried 2007.

  36. 36.

    In re Winship 397 U.S. 358, 371 (1970) (Harlan J. Concurring); Ball 1960, 817; Kaye 1987, 72; Lee 1997, 25; Posner 1999, 1504; Redmayne 1999, 171; Clermont and Sherwin 2002, 268; Stein 2005, 148; Zamir and Ritov 2012, 189; but see Tyree 1982, 93 et seq.

  37. 37.

    Lee 1997, 25.

  38. 38.

    In a strongly worded article, Kevin M. Clermont and Emily Sherwin “rudely wonder how civilians can be so wrong”, Clermont and Sherwin 2002, 244. For an equally strongly worded rebuttal see Taruffo 2003.

  39. 39.

    But see Gottwald 2000, 175; Brinkmann 2005, 3, who argue against any difference in principle between the German and the Common Law’s standard of proof in civil cases.

  40. 40.

    Maassen 1975.

  41. 41.

    Motsch 1978, 335 et seq.; Nell 1983, 211. A precursor, not yet relying on a decision theoretic framework, was Kegel 1967, 335.

  42. 42.

    Walter 1979, 182. In the German original: “Eine Demontage des “Überzeugungserfordernisses” würde also weithin zu einer Korrumpierung der Rechtsmoral in der Bevölkerung führen – wenn schon eine überwiegende Wahrscheinlichkeit genügt, um “einen Prozess zu gewinnen”! Man muss […] will man die Übereinstimmung eines Volkes mit seiner Justiz, den “Konsens” nicht verlieren, auf gewachsene und verankerte Traditionen Rücksicht nehmen.”

  43. 43.

    Berger-Steiner 2008, Rz. 5.131. See also Hohl 1991, 155: “Le degré de vraisemblance à exiger du juge doit être suffisament élevé pour être acceptable sur les plans moral et éthique et légitimer la coercition judiciaire.”

  44. 44.

    Habscheid 1990, 118. In the German original: “Es ist für mich auch fraglich, ob der Gesetzgeber eine solche Regelung einführen kann, ohne an die Wurzeln des Rechtsstaats zu rühren.”

  45. 45.

    In Switzerland, the traditional view has never been under attack in the first place. This is about to change with the publication of my Habilitationsschrift “Beweismaß und Beweiswürdigung. Rationalität und Intuition” Tübingen 2015 (forthcoming).

  46. 46.

    But see Wagner 2009, 172 et seq.

  47. 47.

    Prütting 2010, 142. In the German original: “Es ist nicht zuletzt den klaren und beharrlichen Darlegungen Karl Heinz Schwabs zu danken, dass solche extremen Auffassungen zu keinem Zeitpunkt in der deutschen Rechtswissenschaft Fuß fassen konnten und in keinem Kommentar zur ZPO mehr Erwähnung finden.”

  48. 48.

    Clermont and Sherwin 2002, 269 ff.

  49. 49.

    Tversky and Kahneman 1991 .

  50. 50.

    Tversky and Kahneman 1992, 306 .

  51. 51.

    Kahneman and Tversky 1979, 279 .

  52. 52.

    Kahneman and Tversky 1979, 279 .

  53. 53.

    Tversky and Kahneman 1991 , 154. Tversky and Kahneman 1992, 59, report a median value of about 2.25.

  54. 54.

    Tversky and Kahneman 1992 , 59, suggest that the median of the empirically observed values for the difference in weight of gains and losses is about 2.25.

  55. 55.

    Rachlinski 1996 , 118.

  56. 56.

    Korobkin and Guthrie 1994,133 et seq; Babcock et al. 1995, 296 et seq.; Rachlinski 1996 , 130 et seq.

  57. 57.

    Clermont and Sherwin 2002, 268.

  58. 58.

    Zamir and Ritov 2012, 180.

  59. 59.

    Fehr and Goette 2007, 300; Gächter et al. 2010, 4.

  60. 60.

    This requires the further assumption that the judge—who does not himself or herself gain or lose anything from his or her decision—vicariously experiences the gain or loss of the parties. This assumption is plausible, however, based on research that shows that judges are indeed influenced by the party’s perspective despite having nothing at stake themselves, see Guthrie et al. 2001, 777.

  61. 61.

    Schweizer 2013, 20.

  62. 62.

    Kahneman and Tversky 1982 , 173; Ritov and Baron 1990, 274; Gilovich and Medvec 1995, 380; Prentice and Koehler 2002, 610.

  63. 63.

    Sugarman 1986, 70; Spranca et al. 1991, 82; Kordes-de Vaal 1996, 165; Prentice and Koehler 2002, 593.

  64. 64.

    Ritov and Baron 1995, 124.

  65. 65.

    Kordes-de Vaal 1996, 165; Sunstein 2005, 540.

  66. 66.

    Sunstein 2004, 1582; Birnbacher 1995, 127, but see 209.

  67. 67.

    Kordes-de Vaal 1996, 165.

  68. 68.

    Kahneman and Tversky 1982 , 173.

  69. 69.

    Erroneously here, as throughout this article, means that the claim was granted although it did not exist under the applicable substantive law. It does not mean that the judge made any procedural errors.

  70. 70.

    Zamir and Ritov 2012 , 182.

  71. 71.

    This is the same sample as the one for the study on the influence of loss aversion on the decision threshold . The results will be reported more fully in my forthcoming Habilitationsschrift.

  72. 72.

    t (154) = 3.17, p < 0,01.

  73. 73.

    Samuelson and Zeckhauser 1988, 8; Kahneman et al. 1991 , 197; Schweitzer 1994, 470; Prentice and Koehler 2002, 597; Eidelman and Crandall 2009, 85.

  74. 74.

    Connolly and Zeelenberg 2002, 213.

  75. 75.

    Crandall et al. 2009.

  76. 76.

    Clermont and Sherwin 2002, 268.

  77. 77.

    Rüßmann 1987, n. 21.

  78. 78.

    Stölzel 1913, XXXI.

  79. 79.

    Leipold 1966, 48 et seq.; Prütting 1983, 263 et seq. These days, the consensus view is that it is impossible to reduce the assignment of the burden of proof to a single unifying principle, Ahrens 2008, 29 et seq.; Prütting 2009, n. 42.

  80. 80.

    Kaye 1982, 497.

  81. 81.

    Zamir 2012 , 887 et seq.; Zamir and Ritov 2012, 172. Zamir and Ritov caution, however, against any premature normative conclusions, Zamir and Ritov 2012, 195 et seq.

  82. 82.

    Korobkin and Guthrie 1994, 120 et seq.; Zamir and Ritov 2010 , 262 et seq., 269 (on the malleability of reference points).

  83. 83.

    Zamir 2012, 889 et seq.

  84. 84.

    Redmayne 1999, 174.

  85. 85.

    The fact that in most cases, the car will have been repaired by now makes the argument even stronger.

  86. 86.

    Note that technically, this is not true. If the defendant were a company, it would have to make provisions for the liability at the time of the accident, because the liability exists irrespective of its enforcement by court order.

  87. 87.

    Instead of many after him Mittermaier 1843, 74.

  88. 88.

    See www.worldvaluessurvey.org (last visited 1 February 2014).

  89. 89.

    “I am going to name a number of organizations. For each one, could you tell me how much confidence you have in them: is it a great deal of confidence, quite a lot of confidence, not very much confidence or none at all?”, see WVS 2005 OECD questionnaire, A-Ballot, available from www.worldvaluessurvey.org (last visited 1 February 2014).

  90. 90.

    The figures for the courts are: CH 76.90 %; DE 57.50 %; UK 60.20 %; USA 57.40 %.

  91. 91.

    See Demougin and Fluet 2006; Fluet 2010; Kaplow 2012, 756 et seq.

Bibliography

  • Ahrens, Hans-Jürgen. 2008. Die Verteilung der Beweislast. In Karlsruher Forum 2008: Beweislast, ed. Egon Lorenz, 7–53. Karlsruhe: Verlag Versicherungswirtschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Terence, David A. Schum, and William L. Twining. 2006. Analysis of evidence, 2nd edn. Law in context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Babcock, Linda, Henry S. Farber, Cynthia Fobian, and Eldar Shafir. 1995. Forming beliefs about adjudicated outcomes: Perceptions of risk and reservation values. International Review of Law and Economics 15:289–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ball, V. C. 1960. The moment of truth: Probability theory and standards of proof. Vanderbilt Law Review 14:807–830.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumgärtel, Gottfried. 1996. Beweislastpraxis im Privatrecht. Die Schwierigkeiten der Beweislastverteilung und die Möglichkeiten ihrer Überwindung. Köln: Heymann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bender, Rolf. 1981. Das Beweismaß. In Festschrift für Fritz Baur, ed. Wolfgang Grunsky, Rolf Stürner, Gerhard Walter, and Manfred Wolf, 247–271. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berger-Steiner, Isabelle. 2008. Das Beweismass im Privatrecht. Eine dogmatische Untersuchung mit Erkenntniswert für die Praxis und die Rechtsfigur der Wahrscheinlichkeitshaftung. Bern: Stämpfli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biemann, Torsten. 2009. Logik und Kritik des Hypothesentestens. In Methodik der empirischen Forschung, ed. Sönke Albers, Daniel Klapper, Udo Konradt, Achim Walter, and Joachim Wolf, 205–220. 3rd edn. Wiesbaden: Gabler.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birnbacher, Dieter. 1995. Tun und Unterlassen. Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourmistrov-Jüttner, Elena. 1987. Subjektive Wahrscheinlichkeitstheorie und rationale Entscheidungstheorie in Anwendung auf die Rechtspraxis. Ludwigs-Maximilian University: Munich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brinkmann, Moritz. 2005. Das Beweismaß im Zivilprozess aus rechtsvergleichender Sicht. Köln: Heymann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bühler, Alfred. 2010. Beweismass und Beweiswürdigung bei Gerichtsgutachten—unter Berücksichtigung der jüngsten Lehre und Rechtsprechung. Jusletter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clermont, Kevin M., and Emily Sherwin. 2002. A comparative view of standards of proof. American Journal of Comparative Law 50:243–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, Terry, and Marcel Zeelenberg. 2002. Regret in decision making. Current Directions in Psychological Science 11:212–216. doi:10.2307/20182815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crandall, Christian S., Scott Eidelman, Linda J. Skitka, and G. Scott Morgan. 2009. Status quo framing increases support for torture. Social Influence 4:1–10. doi:10.1080/15534510802124397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cullison, Alan D. 1969. Probability analysis of judicial fact-finding: A preliminary outline of the subjective approach. University of Toledo Law Review 1:538–598.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeKay, Michael L. 1996. The difference between blackstone-like error ratios and probabilistic standards of proof. Law & Social Inquiry 21:95–132. doi:10.1111/j.1747-4469.1996.tb00013.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demougin, Dominique, and Claude Fluet. 2006. Preponderance of evidence. European Economic Review 50:963–976. doi:10.1016/j.euroecorev.2004.11.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deppenkemper, Gunter. 2004. Beweiswürdigung als Mittel prozessualer Wahrheitserkenntnis. Eine dogmengeschichtliche Studie zu Freiheit, Grenzen und revisionsgerichtlicher Kontrolle tatrichterlicher Überzeugungsbildung (§ 261 StPO, § 286 ZPO). Göttingen: V & R Unipress.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eidelman, Scott, and Christian S. Crandall. 2009. A psychological advantage for the status quo. In Social and psychological bases of ideology and system justification, ed. John T. Jost, Aaron C. Kay, and Hulda Thorisdottir, 85–106. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel, Christoph. 2009. Preponderance of the evidence versus intime conviction: A behavioral perspective on a conflict between american and continental european law. Vermont Law Review 33:435–467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, Ernst, and Lorenz Goette. 2007. Do workers work more if wages are high? evidence from a randomized field experiment. American Economic Review 97:298–317. doi:10.2307/30034396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finkelstein, Michael O., and William B. Fairley. 1970. A bayesian approach to identification evidence. Harvard Law Review 83:489–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fluet, Claude. 2010. Liability rules under evidentiary uncertainty. International Review of Law and Economics 30:1–9. doi:10.1016/j.irle.2009.08.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, Bianca. 2005. Das Beweismaß im Arzthaftungsprozess. Frankfurt a. M.: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gächter, Simon, Eric J. Johnson, and Andreas Herrmann. 2010. Individual-level loss aversion in riskless and risky choices. CeDEX discussion paper series.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilovich, Thomas, and Victoria Husted Medvec. 1995. The experience of regret: What, when, and why. Psychological Review 102:379–395. doi:10.1037/0033–295X.102.2.379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gottwald, Peter. 2000. Das flexible Beweismaß im englischen und deutschen Zivilprozess. In Festschrift für Dieter Henrich zum 70. Geburtstag, 1. Dezember 2000, ed. Peter Gottwald, Erik Jayme, and Dieter Schwab, 165–176. Bielefeld: Gieseking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gräns, Minna. 2002. Das Risiko materiell fehlerhafter Urteile. (Diss. Uppsala 1995). Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greger, Reinhard. 1978. Beweis und Wahrscheinlichkeit. Das Beweiskriterium im Allgemeinen und bei den sogenannten Beweiserleichterungen. Köln: Heymann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guthrie, Chris, Jeffrey J. Rachlinski, and Andrew J. Wistrich. 2001. Inside the Judicial Mind. Cornell Law Review 86:777–830.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habscheid, Walther. 1990. Beweislast und Beweismass, ein kontinentaleuropäisch-angelsächsischer Rechtsvergleich. In Festschrift für Gottfried Baumgärtel zum 70. Geburtstag, ed. Hanns Prütting, 105–119. Köln: Carl Heymanns Verlag KG.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohl, Fabienne. 1991. Le degré de la preuve. In Beiträge zum schweizerischen und internationalen Zivilprozeßrecht: Festschrift für Oscar Vogel, ed. Ivo Schwander and Walter Stoffel, 125–159. Freiburg: Univ.-Verl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyer, Andreas. 1993. Der Konflikt zwischen richterlicher Beweiswürdigungsfreiheit und dem Prinzip “in dubio pro reo”. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft 105:523–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kadner Graziano, Thomas. 2011. “Alles oder nichts” oder anteilige Haftung bei Verursachungszweifeln?: Zur Haftung für perte dʼunce chance/loss of chance und eine Alternative. Zeitschrift für Europäisches Recht 19:171–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky. 1979. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica 47:263–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky. 1982. The psychology of preferences. Scientific American 236:160–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel, Jack L. Knetsch, and Richard H. Thaler. 1991. Anomalies: The endowment effect, loss aversion, and status quo bias. Journal of Economic Perspectives 5:193–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, John. 1968. Decision theory and the factfinding process. Stanford Law Review 20:1065–1092.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplow, Louis. 2012. Burden of proof. Yale Law Journal 121:738–859.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaye, David H. 1982. The limits of the preponderance of the evidence standard: Justifiable naked statistical evidence and multiple causation. Law & Social Inquiry 1982:487–516.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaye, David H. 1987. Apples and oranges: Confidence coefficients and the burden of persuasion. Cornell Law Review 73:4–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaye, David H. 2000. Bayes, burdens and base rates. International Journal of Evidence and Proof 4:260–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaye, David H. 2002. The error of equal error rates. Law, Probability & Risk 1:3–8. doi:10.1093/lpr/1.1.3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kegel, Gerhard. 1967. Der Individualanscheinsbeweis und die Verteilung der Beweislast nach überwiegender Wahrscheinlichkeit. In Das Unternehmen in der Rechtsordnung: Festgabe für Heinrich Kronstein aus Anlass seines 70. Geburtstages am 12. September 1967, ed. Kurt H. Biedenkopf, Helmut Coing, and Ernst-Joachim Mestmäcker, 321–344. Karlsruhe: C.F. Müller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kokott, Juliane. 1998. The burden of proof in comparative and international human rights law. Civil and common law approaches with special reference to the American and German legal systems. The Hague: Kluwer Law International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kordes-de Vaal, Johanna H. 1996. Intention and the omission bias: Omissions perceived as nondecisions. Acta Psychologica 93:161–172. doi:10.1016/0001–6918(96)00027-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korobkin, Russell, and Chris Guthrie. 1994. Psychological barriers to litigation settlement: An experimental approach. Michigan Law Review 93:107–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, Thomas R. 1997. Pleading and proof: The economics of legal burdens. Brigham Young University Law Review:1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leipold, Dieter. 1966. Beweislastregeln und gesetzliche Vermutungen insbesondere bei Verweisungen zwischen verschiedenen Rechtsgebieten. Schriften zum Prozessrecht, vol. 4. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lempert, Richard O. 1977. Modeling relevance. Michigan Law Review 75:1021–1057.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lillquist, Erik. 2002. Recasting reasonable doubt: Decision theory and the virtues of variability. U.C. Davis Law Review 36:85–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maassen, Bernhard M. 1975. Beweismaßprobleme im Schadenersatzprozess. Köln: Carl Heymanns Verlag KG.

    Google Scholar 

  • McBride, Ennis. 2009. Is the civil ‘higher standard of proof ʼ a coherent concept? Law, Probability & Risk 8:323–351. doi:10.1093/lpr/mgp011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mittermaier, Carl Joseph Anton. 1843. Die Lehre vom Beweise. Im Deutschen Strafprozesse nach der Fortbildung durch Gerichtsgebrauch und deutsche Gesetzbücher.Johan Wilhelm Heyer’s Verlagshandlung: Darmstadt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Motsch, Richard. 1978. Vom Prozess als Beweis zum Überwiegensprinzip. In Gesetzgebungstheorie, juristische Logik, Zivil- und Prozessrecht: Gedächtnisschrift für Jürgen Rödig, ed. Ulrich Klug, Thilo Ramm, Fritz Rittner, and Burkhard Schmiedel, 334–348. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Motsch, Richard. 1983. Vom rechtsgenügenden Beweis. Zur Entscheidung von Zivilsachen nach Wahrscheinlichkeit unter besonderer Berücksichtigung der Abstammungsfeststellung.Duncker & Humblot: Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Motsch, Richard. 2009. Comparative and analytical remarks on judicial fact-finding. In Festschrift für Gerhard Käfer, ed. Helmut Rüßmann, 241–271. Saarbrücken: Juris GmbH.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musielak, Hans-Joachim. 1975. Die Grundlagen der Beweislast im Zivilprozess. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Stuart, David Lamm, and Marian Neef. 1981. Decision theory and juror decision making. In The trial process (Perspectives in law and psychology, vol. 2, ed. Bruce Dennis Sales, 353–386. New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nell, Ernst Ludwig. 1983. Wahrscheinlichkeitsurteile in juristischen Entscheidungen. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley, Kevin F., Jay E. Grenig, and William C. Lee, eds. 2001. Federal jury practice and instructions. Eagan: Westlaw.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, Roger C., Peter Tillers, Frederick C. Moss, D. Michael Risinger, David H. Kaye, Ronald J. Allen, Samuel R. Gross, Bruce L. Hay, Michael S. Pardo, and Paul F. Kirgis. 2010. Bayes wars redivivus: an exchange. International Commentary on Evidence 8:1–38. doi:10.2202/1554–4567.1115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paulus, Christoph G. 1997. Beweismaß und materielles Recht. In Festschrift für Hans Friedhelm Gaul zum 70. Geburtstag, ed. Eberhard Schilken, Ekkehard Becker-Eberhard, and Walter Gerhardt, 747–760. Bielefeld: Gieseking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, Richard A. 1999. An economic approach to the law of evidence. Stanford Law Review 51:1477–1546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner, Richard A. 2007. Economic analysis of law, 7th edn. Austin: Wolters Kluwer Law & Business.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prentice, Robert A., and Jonathan J. Koehler. 2002. A normality bias in legal decision making. Cornell Law Review 88:583–650.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prütting, Hanns. 1983. Gegenwartsprobleme der Beweislast. Eine Untersuchung moderner Beweislasttheorien und ihrer Anwendung insbesondere im Arbeitsrecht. München: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prütting, Hanns. 2009. Die non-liquet Situation und die Normentheorie. In Handbuch der Beweislast: Grundlagen, ed. Gottfried Baumgärtel, Hans-Willi Laumen, and Hanns Prütting, 135–158, 2nd edn. Köln: Carl Heymanns Verlag KG.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prütting, Hanns. 2010. Beweislast und Beweismaß: Der Einfluss Leo Rosenbergs und Karl Heinz Schwabs auf die Entwicklung eines modernen Beweisrechts. Zeitschrift für Zivilprozess 123:135–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachlinski, Jeffrey J. 1996. Gains, losses and the psychology of litigation. Southern California Law Review 70(1): 113–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Redmayne, Mike. 1999. Standards of proof in civil litigation. Modern Law Review 62:167–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ritov, Ilana, and Jonathan Baron. 1990. Reluctance to vaccinate: Omission bias and ambiguity. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 3:263–277. doi:10.1002/bdm.3960030404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ritov, Ilana, and Jonathan Baron. 1995. Outcome knowledge, regret, and omission bias. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 64:119–127. doi:10.1006/obhd.1995.1094.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, Leo. 1965. Die Beweislast auf der Grundlage des bürgerlichen Gesetzbuchs und der Zivilprozessordnung, 5th edn. München: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rüßmann, Helmut. 1987. vor § 284. In Alternativkommentar zur ZPO, ed. Rudolf Wassermann.Hermann Luchterhand Verlag: Neuwied.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, William, and Richard Zeckhauser. 1988. Status quo bias in decision making. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 1:7–59. doi:10.1007/BF00055564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sand, Leonard B., Jed S. Rakoff, Steven A. Reiss, Walter P. Loughlin, Steven W. Allen, and John S. Siffert, eds. 2007. Modern federal jury instructions—civil volumes. Los Angeles: LexisNexis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweitzer, Maurice. 1994. Disentangling status quo and omission effects: An experimental analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 58:457–476. doi:10.1006/obhd.1994.1046.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schweizer, Mark. 2013. The civil standard of proof—what is it, actually?Preprints of the Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods, Bonn 2013/12

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheppard, Steve. 2003. The metamorphoses of reasonable doubt: How changes in the burden of proof have weakened the presumption of innocence. Notre Dame Law Review 78:1165–1250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spranca, Mark, Elisa Minsk, and Jonathan Baron. 1991. Omission and commission in judgment and choice. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 27:76–105. doi:10.1016/0022-1031(91)90011-T.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Alex. 2005. Foundations of evidence law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stölzel, Adolf. 1913. Schulung für die zivilistische Praxis. 9th edn. Berlin: Vahlen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugarman, David B. 1986. Active versus passive euthanasia: An attributional analysis1. Journal of Applied Social Psychology 16:60–76. doi:10.1111/j.1559-1816.1986.tb02278.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Summermatter, Daniel, and Claudia Jacober. 2012. Zum Beweismass beim Kausal- und Motivationszusammenhang: Versuch einer begrifflichen Klärung anhand der jüngeren Rechtsprechung im Zivil-, Straf- und Sozialversicherungsrecht. HAVE:136–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 2004. Moral herustics and moral framing. Minnesota Law Review 88:1556–1597.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 2005. Moral heuristics. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28:531–541.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taruffo, Michele. 2003. Rethinking the standards of proof. American Journal of Comparative Law 51:659–677.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tillers, Peter, ed. 1988. Probability and inference in the law of evidence. The uses and limits of Bayesianism. Boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 109. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tillers, Peter. 2011. Trial by mathematics—reconsidered. Law, Probability & Risk 10:167–173. doi:10.1093/lpr/mgr011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tillers, Peter, and Jonathan Gottfried. 2007. Case comment–United States v. Copeland, 369 F. Supp. 2d 275 (E.D.N.Y. 2005): A collateral attack on the legal maxim that proof beyond a reasonable doubt is unquantifiable? Law, Probability & Risk 5:135–157. doi:10.1093/lpr/mgl015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tribe, Laurence H. 1971. Trial by mathematics: Precision and ritual in the legal process. Harvard Law Review 84:1329–1393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1991. Loss aversion in riskless choice: A reference-dependent model. Quarterly Journal of Economics 106:1039–1061.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1992. Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 5:297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tyree, Alan L. 1982. Proof and probability in the Anglo-American legal system. Jurimetrics 23:89–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, Gerhard. 2009. Ökonomische Analyse der Rechtsmittel. In Ökonomische Analyse des Verfahrensrechts: Beiträge zum XI. Travemünder Symposium zur Ökonomischen Analyse des Rechts (26. bis 29. März 2008), ed. Reinhard Bork, Thomas Eger, and Hans-Bernd Schäfer, 156–193. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walter, Gerhard. 1979. Freie Beweiswürdigung. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walter, Hans Peter. 2009. Beweis und Beweislast im Haftpflichtprozess. Haftpflichtprozess, 47–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, Richard W. 2009. Proving facts: Belief versus probability. In Tort and insurance law, ed. Helmut Koziol and Barbara C. Steininger, 79–105. Vienna: Springer Vienna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zamir, Eyal. 2012. Loss aversion and the law. Vanderbilt Law Review 65:829–894.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zamir, Eyal, and Ilana Ritov. 2010. Revisiting the debate over attorneysʼ contingent fees: A behavioral analysis. Journal of Legal Studies 39:245–288. doi:10.1086/605510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zamir, Eyal, and Ilana Ritov. 2012. Loss aversion, omission bias, and the burden of proof in civil litigation. Journal of Legal Studies 41:165–207. doi:10.1086/664911.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Schweizer .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schweizer, M. (2015). Loss Aversion, Omission Bias and the Civil Standard of Proof. In: Mathis, K. (eds) European Perspectives on Behavioural Law and Economics. Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-11635-8_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics