Skip to main content

From Rational Choice to Behavioural Economics

Theoretical Foundations, Empirical Findings and Legal Implications

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover European Perspectives on Behavioural Law and Economics

Part of the book series: Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship ((EALELS,volume 2))

Abstract

This article considers how individual decision making is explained in rational choice, on the one hand, and in behavioural economics, on the other hand, and analyses the corresponding implications for the maximization of individual and social utility. Special emphasis is placed on whether and how the law can and shall positively influence non-utility-maximizing behaviour resulting from cognitive heuristics and biases.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Posner 2013, p. 212.

  2. 2.

    Mathis 2009, p. 21 et seqq.

  3. 3.

    Kirchgässner 1988, p. 111 et seqq.

  4. 4.

    Homann and Suchanek 2000, p. 392.

  5. 5.

    See also below, sect. 3.3.

  6. 6.

    Frank 1976, p. 19.

  7. 7.

    Friedman 1953, p. 14.

  8. 8.

    Hotz 1982, p. 304.

  9. 9.

    Posner 1998, p. 18.

  10. 10.

    Posner 1998, p. 18.

  11. 11.

    See Pheby 1988, p. 83.

  12. 12.

    Scriven 1962, p. 176 et seqq.

  13. 13.

    Homann and Suchanek 2000, p. 422.

  14. 14.

    Meyer 1978, p. 41. On Adam Smith’s market optimism see Mathis 2009, p. 108 et seqq.

  15. 15.

    On the efficiency criteria and their philosophical foundations, see Mathis 2009; see also Eidenmüller 2005.

  16. 16.

    Fletcher 1996, p. 158.

  17. 17.

    Baumol 1972, p. 402.

  18. 18.

    See contra Mathis 2009, p. 47 et seqq.

  19. 19.

    Mathis 2007b, p. 1545.

  20. 20.

    For an overview see Mathis 2007a, p. 118–120.

  21. 21.

    This also makes it possible to refute more effectively the objection that economists frequently dedicate their efforts to constructing abstract models in their ivory towers.

  22. 22.

    See e.g. the volume by Camerer, Loewenstein and Rabin 2003; a good overview is also provided by Kahneman 2011.

  23. 23.

    Simon 1979, p. 510.

  24. 24.

    See overall Kahneman and Tversky 1979, p. 263–292.

  25. 25.

    In their paper published in 1974 entitled “Judgement under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases”, Amon Tversky and Daniel Kahneman demonstrated that people rely on mental heuristics in complex decision-making scenarios (this paper is also reproduced in the annex to the book “Thinking, Fast and Slow”).

  26. 26.

    Kahneman 2011, p. 20.

  27. 27.

    Kahneman 2011, p. 21.

  28. 28.

    Tversky and Kahneman 1974, p. 1124.

  29. 29.

    Guthrie, Rachlinski and Wistrich 2001, p. 780.

  30. 30.

    See e.g. Fehr and Fischbacher 2002, C1-C33; Gintis, Bowles, Boyd and Fehr 2005.

  31. 31.

    See Loewenstein 2000, p. 51–76.

  32. 32.

    Tversky and Kahneman 1974, p. 1127.

  33. 33.

    Jolls 2009, p. 77.

  34. 34.

    Jungermann, Pfister and Fischer 2010, p. 173.

  35. 35.

    Jungermann, Pfister and Fischer 2010, p. 174.

  36. 36.

    Jungermann, Pfister and Fischer 2010, p. 174.

  37. 37.

    Fischhoff 1975, p. 292.

  38. 38.

    Fischhoff 1975, p. 288.

  39. 39.

    See Christensen-Szalanski and Fobian-Willham 1991.

  40. 40.

    Rachlinski 2000, p. 97.

  41. 41.

    Rachlinski 2000, p. 97 et seqq.

  42. 42.

    Tversky and Kahneman 1974, p. 1128; Jungermann, Pfister and Fischer 2010, p. 174 et seqq.

  43. 43.

    Tversky and Kahneman 1974, p. 1128.

  44. 44.

    Guthrie, Rachlinski and Wistrich 2001, p. 788.

  45. 45.

    Cf. Jungermann, Pfister and Fischer 2010, p. 175.

  46. 46.

    Schweizer 2005, p. 178.

  47. 47.

    Guthrie, Rachlinski and Wistrich 2001, p. 811 et seqq.

  48. 48.

    Englerth 2007, p. 95.

  49. 49.

    Kahneman and Tversky 1979.

  50. 50.

    A fundamental definition of risk goes back to Frank H. Knight’s paper “Risk, Uncertainty and Profit”. Knight differentiates between the term “risk” as quantitatively measurable uncertainty and the term “uncertainty” for all non-quantifiable uncertainties. Accordingly, a decision will always involve risk if the probability of occurrence is known. By the same token, if the probability of occurrence is unknown, the decision will involve uncertainty (see Knight 1964, p. 19 et seqq.). People react more sensitively to risk than to uncertainty and to events that turn the impossible into the possible or the possible into the certain than to mere increases in likelihood (see Tversky and Fox 1995, p. 269 and 281).

  51. 51.

    Cf. Kahneman und Tversky 1979.

  52. 52.

    Both the endowment effect and the status quo preference are based on loss aversion (cf. Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler 1991, p. 199).

  53. 53.

    Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler 1990.

  54. 54.

    Kahneman and Tversky 1981.

  55. 55.

    See e.g. Jolls and Sunstein 2006.

  56. 56.

    On the law and economics analysis in conjunction with bounded rationality overall, see inter alia Jolls, Sunstein and Thaler 1998, Korobkin and Ulen 2000, Parisi and Smith 2004 and Sunstein 2000.

  57. 57.

    See Rachlinski 2003, p. 1168.

  58. 58.

    Cf. Thaler and Sunstein 2008.

  59. 59.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2008, p. 81 et seqq.

  60. 60.

    However, such an instrument may also be used in order to steer individuals in a politically desirable direction, which may involve more than mere debiasing.

  61. 61.

    Cf. Thaler and Sunstein 2008.

  62. 62.

    See Jolls and Sunstein 2006.

  63. 63.

    See e.g. Stiglitz 1986, p. 90–91.

  64. 64.

    Inter alia, Latin 1994, p. 1243–1244.

  65. 65.

    See e.g. Prentice and Roszkowski 1991–1992.

  66. 66.

    Cf. e.g. Schwartz 1988.

  67. 67.

    Jolls and Sunstein 2006, p. 209–210.

  68. 68.

    Jolls and Sunstein 2006, 216.

  69. 69.

    See e.g. Craig, Sternthal and Leavitt 1976.

  70. 70.

    See e.g. Thomas and Millar 2011, p. 139–149.

  71. 71.

    In actual fact, a study on breast cancer prophylaxis by self-examination showed that stressing the negative effects of failing to carry out self-prophylaxis had a significantly greater impact on behaviour than stressing the positive effects (see Meyerowitz and Chaiken 1987, p. 505).

  72. 72.

    Cf. Jolls and Sunstein 2006.

  73. 73.

    See http://women.americanlegacy.org/about/ads.cfm (visited on 20 April 2014).

  74. 74.

    See e.g. Jolls and Sunstein 2006.

  75. 75.

    Sunstein 2002.

  76. 76.

    Rachlinski 2003, p. 1224.

  77. 77.

    Jolls and Sunstein 2006, p. 225 and 234.

  78. 78.

    Jolls and Sunstein 2006, p. 230.

  79. 79.

    Cf. Jolls and Sunstein 2006, p. 226, see also Rachlinski 2003, p. 1206–1219 and Rasmussen 1998, p. 1697–1698.

  80. 80.

    However, Jolls and Sunstein 2006, p. 232 correctly point out that information can never be entirely neutral since it is inevitable to make linguistic choices when putting thoughts into words. This means that it is virtually impossible to draw a clear line between “neutral information” and “steering manipulation”.

  81. 81.

    Sunstein 2014, p. 158.

  82. 82.

    Cf. Sunstein and Thaler 2003; also see Mitchell 2005.

Bibliography

  • Baumol, William. 1972. Economic theory and operations analysis. 3rd ed., 400–402. London: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, Colin F., George Loewenstein, and Matthew Rabin, eds. 2003. Advances in behavioral economics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen-Szalanski, Jay J., and Cynthia Fobian-Willham. 1991. The hindsight bias: A meta-analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 48:147–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, Samuel, Brian Sternthal, and Clark Leavitt. 1976. Advertising wearout: An experimental analysis. Journal of Market Research 13:365–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eidenmüller, Horst. 2005. Effizienz als Rechtsprinzip. Möglichkeiten und Grenzen der ökonomischen Analyse des Rechts. 3rd ed. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Englerth, Markus. 2007. Behavioral law and economics—eine kritische Einführung. In Recht und Verhalten, eds. Christoph Engel, Markus Englerth, Jörn Lüdemannand, and Indra Spiecker genannt Döhmann, 60–130. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, Ernst, and Urs Fischbacher. 2002. Why social preferences matter—The impact of non-selfish motives on competition, cooperation and incentives. The Economic Journal 112:C1–C33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischhoff, Baruch. 1975. Hindsight ≠ Foresight: The effect of outcome knowledge on judgement under uncertainty. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 1:288–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, George P. 1996. The basic concepts of legal thoughts, 158. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, Jürgen. 1976. Kritische Ökonomie, Einführung in Grundsätze und Kontroversen wirtschaftlicher Theoriebildung. Reinbek: Rowohlt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Milton. 1953. Essays in positive economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gintis, Herbert, Samuel Bowles, Robert Boyd, and Ernst Fehr, eds. 2005. Moral sentiments and material interests. The foundation of cooperation in economic life. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guthrie, Chris, Jeffrey J. Rachlinski, and Andrew J. Wistrich. 2001. Inside the judicial mind. Cornell Law Review 86:777–830.

    Google Scholar 

  • Homann, Karl, and Andreas Suchanek. 2000. Ökonomik: Eine Einführung. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hotz, Beat. 1982. Ökonomische Analyse des Rechts—eine skeptische Betrachtung. Wirtschaft und Recht 34 (4): 293–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jolls, Christine. 2009. Behavioral law and economics. In Law and economics—A reader, ed. Alain Marciano. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jolls, Christine, and Cass R. Sunstein. 2006. Debiasing through law. Journal of Legal Studies 35:199–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jolls, Christine, Cass R. Sunstein, and Richard Thaler. 1998. A behavioral approach to law and economics. Stanford Law Review 50:1471–1550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jungermann, Helmut, Hans-Rüdiger Pfister, and Katrin Fischer. 2010. Die Psychologie der Entscheidung. Eine Einführung. 3rd ed. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel. 2011. Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky. 1979. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica XVLII:263–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky. 1981. The framing of decisions and the psychology of choices. Science 211 (4481): 453–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel, Jack Knetsch, and Richard Thaler. 1990. Experimental tests of the endowment effect and the coase theorem. Journal of Political Economy 98:1325–1348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel, Jack Knetsch, and Richard Thaler. 1991. Anomalies: The endowment effect, loss aversion, and status quo bias. The Journal of Economic Perspectives 5 (1): 193–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, Gebhard. 1988. Die neue Welt der Ökonomie. Analyse und Kritik 10:107–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, Frank H. 1964 (1921). Risk, uncertainty and profit. (Reprint). Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korobkin, Russell, and Thomas Ulen. 2000. Law and behavioral science: Removing the rationality assumption from law and economics. California Law Review 88:1051–1144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latin, Howard. 1994. “Good” warnings, bad products, and cognitive limitations. UCLA Law Review 41:1193–1295.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, George. 2000. Willpower: A decision theorist’s perspective. Law and Philosophy 19:51–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mathis, Klaus. 2007a. Behavioral economics. In Encyclopedia of law and society—American and global perspectives, ed. David S. Clark, vol. 1, 118–120. Thousand Oaks: SAGE Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mathis, Klaus. 2007b. Utility maximization. In Encyclopedia of law and society—American and global perspectives, ed. David S. Clark, vol. 3, 1542–1545. Thousand Oaks: SAGE Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mathis, Klaus. 2009. Effizienz statt Gerechtigkeit? Auf der Suche nach den philosophischen Grundlagen der Ökonomischen Analyse des Rechts. 3rd ed. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot. (Mathis, Klaus. 2009. Efficiency instead of justice? Searching for the philosophical foundations of the economic analysis of law. Dordrecht: Springer.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, Willi. 1978. Die Methodologie der positiven Ökonomie und ihre Folgen. In Neuere Entwicklungen in den Wirtschaftswissenschaften: Verhandlungen auf der Arbeitstagung des Vereins für Socialpolitik, Gesellschaft für Wirtschafts- und Sozialwissenschaften in Münster 1977, ed. Ernst Helmstädter, 19–46. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyerowitz, Beth E., and Shelly Chaiken. 1987. The effect of message framing on breast self-examination: Attitudes, intentions, and behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 52:500–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Gregory. 2005. Libertarian paternalism is an oxymoron. Northwestern University Law Review 99 (3): 1–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parisi, Francesco, and Vernon Smith. 2004. The law and economics of irrational behavior. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pheby, John. 1988. Methodology and economics: A critical introduction. Houndmills: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, Richard A. 1998. Economic analysis of law. 5th ed. New York: Aspen Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, Richard A. 2013. Why is there no Milton Friedman today? Econ Journal Watch 10 (2): 210–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prentice, Robert A., and Mark E. Roszkowski. 1991–1992. “Tort reform” and the liability “revolution”: Defending strict liability in tort for defective products. Gonzaga Law Review 27:251–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachlinski, Jeffrey J. 2000. A positive psychological theory of judging in hindsight. In Behavioral law and economics, ed. Cass R. Sunstein, 95–115. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachlinski, Jeffrey J. 2003. The uncertain psychological case for paternalism. Northwestern University Law Review 97 (3): 1165–1225.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen, Robert K. 1998. Behavioral economics, the economic analysis of bankruptcy law, and the pricing of credit. Vanderbilt Law Review 51:1679–1703.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, Alan. 1988. Proposal for products liability reform: A theoretical synthesis. Yale Law Journal 97:353–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweizer, Mark. 2005. Kognitive Täuschungen vor Gericht. Eine empirische Studie. Zürich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scriven, Michael. 1962. Explanations, predictions and law. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 2:170–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, Herbert A. 1979. Rational decision making in business organizations. American Economic Review 69:493–513.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz, Joseph E. 1986. Economics of the Public Sector. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R., ed. 2000. Behavioral law and economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 2002. Probability neglect: Emotions, worst cases, and law. Yale Law Journal 112:61–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 2003. Why societies need dissent. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 2014. Why nudge? New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R., and Richard H. Thaler. 2003. Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. The University of Chicago Law Review 70 (4): 1159–1202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, Richard H., and Cass R. Sunstein. 2008. Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth and happiness. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, Ayanna K., and Peter R. Millar. 2011. Reducing the framing effect in older and younger adults by encouraging analytic processing. The Journals of Gerontology Series B: Psychological Sciences and Social Sciences 67B (2): 139–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos, and Craig R. Fox. 1995. Weighing risk and uncertainty. Psychological Review 102 (2): 269–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1974. Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science (New Series) 185 (4157): 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to sincerely thank Thomas Roberts for his translation as well as Julia Wetzel, MLaw, Luca Langensand, MLaw, and Philipp Anton Burri for their careful proofreading.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Klaus Mathis .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mathis, K., Steffen, A. (2015). From Rational Choice to Behavioural Economics. In: Mathis, K. (eds) European Perspectives on Behavioural Law and Economics. Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-11635-8_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics