Skip to main content

European and American Perspectives on Behavioural Law and Economics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
European Perspectives on Behavioural Law and Economics

Part of the book series: Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship ((EALELS,volume 2))

Abstract

Behavioural law and economics is one of the two most significant developments currently going on in legal scholarship. In this essay, I seek to describe, first, why behavioural law and economics is so important and to give a brief example of how it has altered the law-and-economic analysis of one significant area of substantive law—criminal law and punishment. Second, I discuss some criticisms of behavioural law and economics, finding that some of those criticisms have merit and raise serious issues that legal scholars should investigate further. I describe two recent articles that find a common behavioural policy prescription of using “nudges” to be not just ineffectual but damaging. Finally, I speculate on some differences between the structure of legal faculties and prevailing scholarly practices in Europe and North America that may have an impact on how quickly legal scholars in those two areas address the open questions in behavioural law and economics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The other important trend in legal scholarship, one closely related to behavioural law and economics, is empirical legal studies.

  2. 2.

    Pessendorf 2006. There are, of course, significant exceptions to this characterization. John List at the University of Chicago, Matthew Rabin at the University of California, Berkeley, Sendhil Mullainathan at Harvard, and others have been prominent in their use of behavioural economics. I also believe that it is true that European economists have been more congenially disposed toward behavioural economics than have North American economists.

  3. 3.

    The only exception to this statement of which I am aware is Frank 2014.

  4. 4.

    I recall that when I first began presenting papers to law faculties in the early 1980s and would begin my presentation by saying that I would be assuming rational choice by decisionmakers, someone would ask some version of the question, “Who are these rational decisionmakers you’re talking about?”

  5. 5.

    Thomas Kuhn 1996.

  6. 6.

    There is, of course, a downside to this willingness. The field must develop a sense for what innovations have promise and make sense and which do not. The experience of law with one innovation of the late 1980s and early 1990s—critical legal studies—illustrates that law is able to make this distinction between promising and unpromising innovations.

  7. 7.

    Garoupa and Ulen 2008.

  8. 8.

    Another Newton quote that is apt: “Men build too many walls and not enough bridges.” Law seems to have been building bridges to other disciplines more than almost any other social science, with the predictable result that there is a very high level of intellectual fervor in legal scholarship, at least in North America.

  9. 9.

    In European terms, law and economics seems to be associated with neo-liberal political views. In U.S. terms, the association would be said to be with conservative or neo-conservative politics.

  10. 10.

    The expected costs of crime are the product of the probabilities of detection, arrest, and conviction and the value of the sanctions imposed on the guilty criminal. Becker implied that, all other things being equal, it was more efficient to raise those expected costs by raising the value of the sanction rather than by raising the probabilities of detection, arrest, and conviction.

  11. 11.

    Through the 1980s state and federal sentencing guidelines moved from a system of indeterminate sentencing (under which judges had a range within which to sentence a convicted criminal for a given crime, with the judge having discretion as to where within that range to place any given criminal; additionally, parole boards had discretion to release convicted criminals who had not completed their sentence but had exhibited some desirable behavior during imprisonment) to one of determinate sentencing (under which judges had relatively little discretion in sentencing, and parole boards virtually went out of business).

  12. 12.

    The very large numbers of prisoners in U.S. jails and prisons peaked in 2007 and has declined slightly since then.

  13. 13.

    Donohue and Levitt 2001; Levitt 2004; Zimring 2008.

  14. 14.

    Donohue and Levitt attributed half of that 50 % explanation to the fact that there were fewer 18-year-old men in the population as of 1991 and another half to the fact that the young men born in the years after 1973 were less likely to commit crime than the young men who were not born. Cooter and Ulen 2012, Ch. 12.

  15. 15.

    Raphael and Stoll 2014.

  16. 16.

    Raphael and Stoll 2014, p. 17.

  17. 17.

    Robinson and Darley 2004.

  18. 18.

    Barbarino and Mastrobuoni 2014.

  19. 19.

    For example, Ehrlich 1975; Cooter and Ulen 2012, Ch. 13.

  20. 20.

    See Donohue and Wolfers 2005.

  21. 21.

    Cooter 2011.

  22. 22.

    Thaler and Sunstein 2008.

  23. 23.

    List 2003, 2006, 2008.

  24. 24.

    Becker 1962.

  25. 25.

    Mitchell 2002a, b, 2005, 2009.

  26. 26.

    Mitchell and Klick 2006.

  27. 27.

    Mitchell 2002a, p. 73.

  28. 28.

    Mitchell 2009.

  29. 29.

    This topic is one of the central concerns in Kahneman 2011. Kahneman distinguishes between System I thinking, which is quick, intuitive, and capable of generating a rapid response, and System II thinking, which is slow, deliberative, balanced, and interested in getting the right response. There is a popular literature, Gladwell 2005, and a scholarly literature, Gigerenzer 2007, that is far more well-disposed toward intuition, as being a form of crystallized experience.

  30. 30.

    Mitchell and Klick 2006.

  31. 31.

    Spector 2012; Rebonato 2013; Conly 2013.

  32. 32.

    Vandenbergh et al. 2011; Robinson and Hammit 2011; Sunstein 2013. The central behavioural finding that argued in favor of changing the default as a “nudge” was the discovery that people do not typically move away from a default position; those defaults, in the parlance of the literature, are said to be “sticky.” The results of changing the default can be large, without much apparent change in the well-being of those subject to the default. So, for example, the choice between an opt-out regime for donating one’s organs for transplantation (the organs are presumed not to be available for transplantation unless the donor takes steps to opt out of donation) and an opt-in system (in which the donor’s organs are presumed not to be available unless the donor takes steps to opt in to the transplantation system) may seem to be inconsequential. But the differences are profound: The U.S. has an opt-in system and only about 28 % of people take steps to do so. By contrast, in the six European countries that have an opt-out system, the donation rates vary between 85 and 99 + percent.

  33. 33.

    Bubb and Pildes 2014.

  34. 34.

    Schwartz Center for Economic Policy Analysis, Department of Economics, The New School 2012. Retirement account balances by income: Even the highest earners don’t have enough. http://www.economicpolicyresearch.org/guaranteeing-retirement-income/528-retirement-account-balances-by-income-even-the-highest-earners-dont-have-enough.html. The more detailed figures are even more startling. For the two lowest personal income quartiles (those with annual incomes of less than $ 27,500), the mean total savings for those who are 50–64 years of age in the lowest quartile are $ 16,034, with a median of $ 0; for those who are 50–64 in the next highest quartile, the median total savings are $ 21,606, with a median of $ 0. For those in the highest quartile (annual personal income of greater than $ 52,201) the mean total savings are $ 105,012, with a median of $ 52,000. For the purposes of rough accounting, most financial planners suggest total savings equal to 20 times one’s annual income on the eve of retirement as a prudent amount.

  35. 35.

    Bubb and Pildes 2014, p. 7.

  36. 36.

    Bubb and Pildes consider two additional instances in which individuals make decisions that are either sub-optimal for themselves or for society or both and in which nudges have been recommended as corrective but do not work.

  37. 37.

    Willis 2013.

  38. 38.

    When I joined the law school faculty in 1982, I was the first person to have a Ph.D. (and only a Ph.D.) to join that faculty since the founding of the law school in 1897.

Bibliography

  • Barbarino, Alessandro, and Giovanni Mastrobuoni. 2014. The incapacitation effect of incarceration: Evidence from several Italian collective pardons. American Economic Journal of Economic Policy 6:1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, Gary S. 1962. Irrational behavior and economic theory. Journal of Political Economy 70:1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, Gary S. 1968. Crime and punishment: An economic analysis. Journal of Political Economy 76:169–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bubb, Ryan, and Richard H. Pildes. 2014. How behavioral economics trims its sails and why. Harvard Law Review 127:1593–1678.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conly, Sarah. 2013. Against autonomy: Justifying coercive paternalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooter, Robert D. 2011. Maturing into normal science: The effect of empirical legal studies on law and economics. University of Illinois Law Review 2011:1475–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooter, Robert D., and Thomas S. Ulen. 2012. Law and economics. 6th ed. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donohue III, John J., and Steven D. Levitt. 2001. The impact of legalized abortion on crime. Quarterly Journal of Economics 116:379–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donohue III, John J., and Justin Wolfers. 2005. Uses and abuses of emprical evidence in the death penalty debate. Stanford Law Review 58:791–845.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehrlich, Isaac. 1975. The deterrent effect of capital punishment: A question of life and death. American Economic Review 65:397–417.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, Robert H. 2014. Microeconomics and behavior. 9th ed. New York: McGraw-Hill/Irwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garoupa, Nuno, and Thomas S. Ulen. 2008. The market for legal innovation: Law and economics in Europe and the United States. Alabama Law Review 59:1555–1633.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, Gerd. 2007. Gut feelings: The intelligence of the unconscious. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gladwell, Malcolm. 2005. Blink: The power of thinking without thinking. Boston: Little Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel. 2011. Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas. 1996. The structure of scientific revolutions. 3rd ed. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levitt, Steven D. 2004. Understanding why crime fell in the 1990s: Four factors that explain the decline and six that do not. Journal of Economic Perspectives 18:163–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, John A. 2003. Does market experience eliminate market anomalies? Quarterly Journal of Economics 118:41–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, John A. 2006. The behavioralist meets the market: Measuring social preferences and reputation effects in actual transactions. Journal of Political Economy 114:1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, John A., and Daniel L. Millimet. 2008. The market: Catalyst for rationality and filter of irrationality. Berkeley Electronic Journal of Economic Analysis and Policy 8:1–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Gregory. 2002a. Why law and economics’ perfect rationality should not be traded for behavioral law and economics’ equal incompetence. Georgetown Law Journal 91:67–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Gregory. 2002b. Taking behavioralism too seriously? The unwarranted pessimism of the new behavioral analysis of law. William & Mary Law Review 43:1907–2021.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Gregory. 2005. Libertarian paternalism is an oxymoron. Northwestern Law Review 99:1245–1278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Gregory. 2009. Second thoughts. McGeorge Law Review 40:687–722.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Gregory, and Jonathan Klick. 2006. Government regulation of irrationality: Moral and cognitive hazards. Minnesota Law Review 90:1621–1663.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pessendorf, Wolfgang. 2006. Behavioral economics comes of age: A review essay of advances in behavioral economics. Journal of Economic Literature 44:712–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raphael, Steven, and Michael A. Stoll. 2014. A new approach to reducing incarceration while maintaining low rates of crime. The Hamilton Project, Discussion Paper 14-03. Washington: The Brookings Institution 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rebonato, Riccardo. 2013. A critical assessment of libertarian paternalism. Working Paper 1-68, University of Oxford and University of Edinburgh. www.ssrn.com. Accessed 8 June 2014.

  • Robinson, Paul H., and John M. Darley. 2004. Does criminal law deter? A behavioral science investigation. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 24:173–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, Lisa A., and James K. Hammitt. 2011. Behavioral economics and regulatory analysis. Risk Analysis 31:1408–1422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spector, Horacio. 2012. Autonomy. In The routledge companion to social and political philosophy, ed. Gerald F. Gauss and Fred D’Agostino, 573–584. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass R. 2013. Simpler: The future of government. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, Richard H., and Cass R. Sunstein. 2008. Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness (Revised ed.) New York: The Penguin Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vandenbergh, Michael P., Lisa S. Bressman, and Amanda Carrico. 2011. Regulation in the behavioral era. Minnesota Law Review 95:715–781.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willis, Lauren E. 2013. When nudges fail: Slippery defaults. University of Chicago Law Review 80:1155–1229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimring, Franklin E. 2008. The great American crime decline. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

I want to thank Avishalom Tor and Klaus Mathis for organizing the Lucerne conference and inviting me to attend. I also want to thank Julia Wetzel, Ariel Steffen, and the IT people at Lucerne and Tyler Hunter at Illinois for arranging for me to speak to the conference by video.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas S. Ulen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ulen, T. (2015). European and American Perspectives on Behavioural Law and Economics. In: Mathis, K. (eds) European Perspectives on Behavioural Law and Economics. Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-11635-8_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics