Skip to main content

Exhaustivity Through the Maxim of Relation

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence (JSAI-isAI 2013)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNAI,volume 8417))

Included in the following conference series:

  • 923 Accesses

Abstract

I show that the exhaustive interpretation of answers can be explained as a conversational implicature through the Maxim of Relation, dealing with the problematic epistemic step (Sauerland 2004). I assume a fairly standard Maxim of Relation, that captures the same intuition as Roberts’ (1996) contextual entailment. I show that if a richer notion of meaning is adopted, in particular that of attentive semantics (Roelofsen 2011), this Maxim of Relation automatically becomes strong enough to enable exhaustivity implicatures. The results suggest that pragmatic reasoning is sensitive not only to the information an utterance provides, but also to the possibilities it draws attention to. Foremost, it shows that exhaustivity implicatures can be genuine conversational implicatures.

(Cannot access the full version? Download it from the author’s website.)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For brevity, I will typically use the word ‘know’ (and, likewise, ‘knowledge’) as if saying ‘taking oneself to know’, i.e., without requiring the usual factivity associated with knowledge as being ‘true belief’.

  2. 2.

    Groenendijk and Stokhof [10] already argued that exhaustivity cannot be derived through the Maxim of Quantity alone. After all, the Quantity implicature says ‘this is as informative as I can safely be’, hence it can never be used to strengthen what is said, as is required for the epistemic step. The contrast in (2) supports this view from a different angle: it’s not only quantity of information that matters.

  3. 3.

    The difference between positively and negatively exhaustive answers fades if the question under discussion is a partition. Given Groenendijk and Stokhof’s argument, I take this as strong evidence that, in general, questions (at least those in response to which a non-exhaustive answer would implicate exhaustivity) are not partitions; i.e., they have existential force, i.e., draw attention to their mention-some answers, rather than universal force.

  4. 4.

    This shows that, in this case, the Relation implicature in fact clashes with the Quantity implicature: for if the speaker really knows whether John was at the party, then why didn’t she just say so? As a consequence, the example will likely trigger additional implicatures to explain this clash, e.g., that the speaker wants to test the hearer’s knowledge. (Understandably, therefore, the example under discussion is more natural with a final rising pitch contour, which has been argued to convey uncertain relevance/relatedness [18].) Regardless of this, the example suffices for merely illustrating how the Maxim of Relation works.

  5. 5.

    The speaker can be competent in two ways, and in the case of exhaustivity, the Quality and Quantity implicatures together settle how (something which did not happen in the rainy party example). This shows that, as mentioned above, it would be too strict to require that the hearer already knows how a response is related to the question; in the case of exhaustivity, the Quality and Quantity implicatures enable her to figure it out.

  6. 6.

    In the future I hope to give such general descriptions of the Relation implicature also for cases where the response is any (potentially non-singleton) subset of the question, as these are all and only the cases that may yield exhaustivity implicatures. However, so far the results for such question-response pairs have not turned out any more readable than the general characterisation in (10), and I will omit them.

  7. 7.

    This possible objection was brought to my attention by Donka Farkas.

References

  1. Alonso-Ovalle, L.: Disjunction in alternative semantics. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Büring, D.: On d-trees, beans, and accents. Linguist. Philos. 26, 511–545 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Chierchia, G., Fox, D., Spector, B.: The grammatical view of scalar implicatures and the relationship between semantics and pragmatics. In: Maienborn, C., Portner, P., von Heusinger, K. (eds.) Semantics: An International Handbook of Natural Language Meaning, vol. 2, pp. 2297–2332. Mouton de Gruyter, Boston (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ciardelli, I.: Inquisitive semantics and intermediate logics. Master Thesis, University of Amsterdam (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ciardelli, I., Groenendijk, J., Roelofsen, F.: Attention! Might in inquisitive semantics. In: Ito, S., Cormany, E., (eds.) Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory, SALT XIX (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Coppock, E., Brochhagen, T.: Raising and resolving issues with scalar modifiers. Semant. Pragmat. 6, 1–57 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Geurts, B.: Quantity Implicatures. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Grice, H.: Logic and conversation. In: Cole, P., Morgan, J. (eds.) Syntax and Semantics, vol. 3, pp. 41–58. Academic Press, New York (1975)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Groenendijk, J., Roelofsen, F.: Inquisitive semantics and pragmatics. In: Larrazabal, J.M., Zubeldia, L., (eds.) Meaning, Content, and Argument: Proceedings of the ILCLI International Workshop on Semantics, Pragmatics, and Rhetoric (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Groenendijk, J., Stokhof, M.: Studies on the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Horn, L.: Towards a new taxonomy of pragmatic inference: Q-based and R-based implicatures. In: Schiffrin, D. (ed.) Meaning, Form, and Use in Context, pp. 11–42. Georgetown University Press, Washington (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Mill, J.S.: An examination of Sir William Hamiltons philosophy (1867)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Roberts, C.: Information structure in discourse. In: Yoon, J., Kathol, A. (eds.) OSU Working Papers in Linguistics, vol. 49, pp. 91–136. Ohio State University, Columbus (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Roelofsen, F.: Information and attention (Manuscript, ILLC University of Amsterdam (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Sauerland, U.: Scalar implicatures in complex sentences. Linguist. Philos. 27(3), 367–391 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Schulz, K., van Rooij, R.: Pragmatic meaning and non-monotonic reasoning: the case of exhaustive interpretation. Linguist. Philos. 29, 205–250 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Spector, B.: Scalar implicatures: exhaustivity and Gricean reasoning. In: Aloni, M., Butler, A., Dekker, P. (eds.) Questions in Dynamic Semantics, pp. 225–250. Elsevier, Oxford (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ward, G., Hirschberg, J.: Implicating uncertainty: the pragmatics of fall-rise intonation. Language 61(4), 747–776 (1985)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Westera, M.: Meanings as proposals: a new semantic foundation for Gricean pragmatics. In: Proceedings of SemDial 2012 (2012)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Jeroen Groenendijk, Floris Roelofsen, Donka Farkas, Kai von Fintel, Chris Cummins, the audiences of SPE6 (St. Petersburg), S-Circle (UC Santa Cruz), ESSLLI Student Session 2013 (Düsseldorf), LIRA (Amsterdam), TbiLLC 2013 (Gudauri) and many anonymous reviewers for very helpful comments. Financial support from the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research is gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthijs Westera .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this paper

Cite this paper

Westera, M. (2014). Exhaustivity Through the Maxim of Relation. In: Nakano, Y., Satoh, K., Bekki, D. (eds) New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence. JSAI-isAI 2013. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 8417. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-10061-6_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-10061-6_10

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-10060-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-10061-6

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics